283 research outputs found

    Does Liberal Egalitarianism Depend on a Theology?

    Get PDF

    Jeffrey Stout, DEMOCRACY AND TRADITION

    Get PDF

    Nicholas Wolterstorff, JUSTICE IN LOVE

    Get PDF

    May Clergy Seek Elective Office

    Get PDF

    Joseph Runzo, ed., ETHICS, RELIGION AND THE GOOD SOCIETY: NEW DIRECTIONS IN A PLURALISTIC WORLD

    Get PDF

    R. Bruce Douglass and David Hollenbach, eds., CATHOLICISM AND LIBERALISM

    Get PDF

    May Clergy Seek Elective Office

    Get PDF

    The Fragility of Consensus: Public Reason, Diversity and Stability

    Get PDF
    John Rawls\u27s transition from A Theory of Justice to Political Liberalism was driven by his rejection of Theory\u27s account of stability. The key to his later account of stability is the idea of public reason. We see Rawls\u27s account of stability as an attempt to solve a mutual assurance problem. We maintain that Rawls\u27s solution fails because his primary assurance mechanism, in the form of public reason, is fragile. His conception of public reason relies on a condition of consensus that we argue is unrealistic in modern, pluralistic democracies. After rejecting Rawls\u27s conception of public reason, we offer an ‘indirect alternative’ that we believe is much more robust. We cite experimental evidence to back up this claim

    Christian Realism and Augustinian (?) Liberalism

    Get PDF
    Surely there is enough kindling lying about in the Bible and in subsequent moral theology to fire up love for neighbors and compassion for countless “friends” in foreign parts--and in crisis. And, surely, the momentum of love’s labor for the just redistribution of resources, fueled by activists’ appeals for solidarity, should be sustained by stressing that we are creatures made for affection, not for aggression. Yet experience, plus the history of the Christian traditions, taught Reinhold Niebuhr, who memorably reminded Christian realists, how often love was “defeated,” how a “strategy of brotherhood . . . degenerates from mutuality to a prudent regard for the interests of self and from an impulse towards community to an acceptance of the survival impulse as ethically normative” (Niebuhr 1964, 2:96). But he was encouraged after reading Augustine. The late antique African bishop nudged Niebuhr to look for the “formula for leavening the city of this world with the love of the city of God” (Niebuhr 1953, 134). The authors of the books before us are still looking. They concede, as did Niebuhr, that Augustine’s monumental City of God explicitly sets limits on love’s effectiveness on the practice of politics. They refuse, nonetheless, as did Niebuhr, to offer any “blanket judgments about the power of the state,” although they acknowledge that politics tends to trick practitioners to overlook limits and to become “idolatrous[ly]” infatuated with what governments can do (Lovin 1995, 180-84; Lovin 2008, 198-99)
    corecore