12,310 research outputs found

    The Kantian Framework of Complementarity

    Get PDF
    A growing number of commentators have, in recent years, noted the important affinities in the views of Immanuel Kant and Niels Bohr. While these commentators are correct, the picture they present of the connections between Bohr and Kant is painted in broad strokes; it is open to the criticism that these affinities are merely superficial. In this essay, I provide a closer, structural, analysis of both Bohr's and Kant's views that makes these connections more explicit. In particular, I demonstrate the similarities between Bohr's argument, on the one hand, that neither the wave nor the particle description of atomic phenomena pick out an object in the ordinary sense of the word, and Kant's requirement, on the other hand, that both 'mathematical' (having to do with magnitude) and 'dynamical' (having to do with an object's interaction with other objects) principles must be applicable to appearances in order for us to determine them as objects of experience. I argue that Bohr's 'Complementarity interpretation' of quantum mechanics, which views atomic objects as idealizations, and which licenses the repeal of the principle of causality for the domain of atomic physics, is perfectly compatible with, and indeed follows naturally from a broadly Kantian epistemological framework.Comment: Slight change between this version and previous in the wording of the first paragraph of the section 'Complementarity

    Interpretation of Coulomb breakup of 31Ne in terms of deformation

    Full text link
    The recent experimental data on Coulomb breakup of the nucleus 31^{31}Ne are interpreted in terms of deformation. The measured large one-neutron removal cross-section indicates that the ground state of 31^{31}Ne is either s- or p-halo. The data can be most easily interpreted as the spin of the ground state being 3/2−^- coming from either the Nilsson level [330 1/2] or [321 3/2] depending on the neutron separation energy SnS_n. However, the possibility of 1/2+^{+} coming from [200 1/2] is not excluded. It is suggested that if the large ambiguity in the measured value of SnS_n of 31^{31}Ne, 0.29±1.64\pm1.64 MeV, can be reduced by an order of magnitude, say to be ±\pm100 keV, one may get a clear picture of the spin-parity of the halo ground state.Comment: 8 pages, 4 figure

    Complementarity and Scientific Rationality

    Get PDF
    Bohr's interpretation of quantum mechanics has been criticized as incoherent and opportunistic, and based on doubtful philosophical premises. If so Bohr's influence, in the pre-war period of 1927-1939, is the harder to explain, and the acceptance of his approach to quantum mechanics over de Broglie's had no reasonable foundation. But Bohr's interpretation changed little from the time of its first appearance, and stood independent of any philosophical presuppositions. The principle of complementarity is itself best read as a conjecture of unusually wide scope, on the nature and future course of explanations in the sciences (and not only the physical sciences). If it must be judged a failure today, it is not because of any internal inconsistency.Comment: 29 page

    Perturbative quantum damping of cosmological expansion

    Get PDF
    Perturbative quantum gravity in the framework of the Schwinger–Keldysh formalism is applied to compute lowest-order corrections to expansion of the Universe described in terms of the spatially flat Friedman–Lemaître–Robertson–Walker solution. The classical metric is approximated by a third degree polynomial perturbation around the Minkowski metric. It is shown that quantum contribution to the classical expansion, though extremely small, damps, i.e. slows down, the expansion (phenomenon of quantum friction)
    • …
    corecore