7 research outputs found
Neural signatures for sustaining object representations attributed to others in preverbal human infants
A major feat of
social beings is to encode what their conspecifics see, know or believe.
While various nonhuman animals show precursors of these abilities, humans perform
uniquely sophisticated inferences about other peopleâs mental states. However, it is still
unclear how these possibly human-specific capacities develop and whether preverbal
infants, similarly to adults form representations of other agentsâ mental states, specifically
metarepresentations. We explored the neuro-cognitive bases of 8-month-oldsâ ability to
encode the world from another personâs perspective, using gamma-band EEG activity over
the temporal lobes, an established neural signature for sustained object representation
after occlusion. We observed such gamma-band activity when an object was occluded
from the infantsâ perspective, as well as when it was occluded only from the other person
(Experiment 1), and also when subsequently the object disappeared but the person falsely
believed the object to be present (Experiment 2). These findings suggest that the cognitive
systems involved in representing the world from infantsâ own perspective are also recruited
for encoding othersâ beliefs. Such results point to an early developing, powerful apparatus
suitable to deal with multiple concurrent representations; and suggest that infants can
have a metarepresentational understanding of other minds even before the onset of
language
Can infants adopt underspecified contents into attributed beliefs? Representational prerequisites of theory of mind
Recent evidence suggests that young infants, as well as nonhuman apes, can anticipate othersâ behavior based on their false beliefs. While such behaviors have been proposed to be accounted by simple associations between agents, objects, and locations, human adults are undoubtedly endowed with sophisticated theory of mind abilities. For example, they can attribute mental contents about abstract or non-existing entities, or beliefs whose content is poorly specified. While such endeavors may be human specific, it is unclear whether the representational apparatus that allows for encoding such beliefs is present early in development. In four experiments we asked whether 15-month-old infants are able to attribute beliefs with underspecified content, update their content later, and maintain attributed beliefs that are unknown to be true or false. In Experiment 1, infants observed as an agent hid an object to an unspecified location. This location was later revealed in the absence or presence of the agent, and the object was then hidden again to an unspecified location. Then the infants could search for the object while the agent was away. Their search was biased to the revealed location (that could be represented as the potential content of the agentâs belief when she had not witnessed the re-hiding), suggesting that they (1) first attributed an underspecified belief to the agent, (2) later updated the content of this belief, and (3) were primed by this content in their own action even though its validity was unknown. This priming effect was absent when the agent witnessed the re-hiding of the object, and thus her belief about the earlier location of the object did not have to be sustained. The same effect was observed when infants searched for a different toy (Experiment 2) or when an additional spatial transformation was introduced (Experiment 4), but not when the spatial transformation disrupted belief updating (Experiment 3). These data suggest that infantsâ representational apparatus is prepared to efficiently track other agentsâ beliefs online, encode underspecified beliefs and define their content later, possibly reflecting a crucial characteristic of mature theory of mind: using a metarepresentational format for ascribed beliefs
Young domestic chicks spontaneously represent the absence of objects
Absence is a notion that is usually captured by language-related concepts like zero or negation. Whether nonlinguistic creatures encode similar thoughts is an open question, as everyday behavior marked by absence (of food, of social partners) can be explained solely by expecting presence somewhere else. We investigated 8-day-old chicksâ looking behavior in response to events violating expectations about the presence or absence of an object. We found different behavioral responses to violations of presence and absence, suggesting distinct underlying mechanisms. Importantly, chicks displayed an avian signature of novelty detection to violations of absence, namely a sex-dependent left-eye-bias. Follow-up experiments excluded accounts that would explain this bias by perceptual mismatch or by representing the object at different locations. These results suggest that the ability to spontaneously form representations about the absence of objects likely belongs to the initial cognitive repertoire of vertebrate species