2,287 research outputs found
Lines of Descent: Kuhn and Beyond
yesThomas S. Kuhn is famous both for his work on the Copernican Revolution and his âparadigmâ view of scientific revolutions. But Kuhn later abandoned the notion of paradigm (and related notions) in favour of a more âevolutionaryâ view of the history of science. Kuhnâs position therefore moved closer to âcontinuityâ models of scientific progress, for instance âchain-of-reasoningâ models, originally championed by D. Shapere. The purpose of this paper is to contribute to the debate around Kuhnâs new âdevelopmentalâ view and to evaluate these competing models with reference to some major innovations in the history of cosmology, from Copernicanism to modern cosmology. This evaluation is made possible through some unexpected overlap between Kuhnâs earlier discontinuity model and various versions of the later continuity models. It is the thesis of this paper that the âchain-of-reasoningâ model accounts better for the cosmological evidence than both Kuhnâs early paradigm model and his later developmental view of the history of science
Metacognition and Abstract Concepts
The problem of how concepts can refer to or be about the nonâmental world is
particularly puzzling for abstract concepts. There is growing evidence that many
characteristics beyond the perceptual are involved in grounding different kinds of
abstract concept. A resource that has been suggested, but little explored, is
introspection. This paper develops that suggestion by focusing specifically on
metacognitionâon the thoughts and feelings that thinkers have about a concept. One
example of metacognition about concepts is the judgement that we should defer to
others in how a given concept is used. Another example is our internal assessment of
which concepts are dependable and useful, and which less so. Metacognition of this
kind may be especially important for grounding abstract concepts
Reductions in global biodiversity loss predicted from conservation spending
Halting global biodiversity loss is central to both the Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD) and United Nations Sustainable Development Goals (SDGs)1,2, but success to date has been very limited3â5. A critical determinant of overall strategic success (or failure) is the financing committed to biodiversity6â9; however, financing decisions are still hindered by considerable uncertainty over what any investment is likely to achieve6â9.. For greater effectiveness, we need an evidence-based model (EBM)10â12 showing how conservation spending quantitatively reduces the rate of loss. Here, we empirically quantify how i$14.4 billion of conservation investment reduced biodiversity loss across 109 signatory countries between 1996 and 2008, by an average 29% per country. We also show that biodiversity change in signatory countries can be predicted with high accuracy, using a dual model that combines the positive impact of conservation investment with the negative impact of economic, agricultural and population growth (i.e. human development pressures)13â18. Decision-makers can use this dual model to forecast the improvement that any proposed biodiversity budget would achieve under various scenarios of human development pressure, comparing those forecasts to any chosen policy target (including the CBD and SDGs). Importantly, we further find that spending impacts shrink as human development pressures grow, implying that funding may need to increase over time. The model therefore offers a flexible tool for balancing the SDGs of human development and biodiversity, by predicting the dynamic changes needed in conservation finance as human development proceeds
Mind before matter: reversing the arrow of fundamentality
In this contribution to FQXi's essay contest 2018, I suggest that it is
sometimes a step forward to reverse our intuition on "what is fundamental", a
move that is somewhat reminiscent of the idea of noncommutative geometry. I
argue that some foundational conceptual problems in physics and related fields
motivate us to attempt such a reversal of perspective, and to take seriously
the idea that an information-theoretic notion of observer ("mind") could in
some sense be more fundamental than our intuitive idea of a physical world
("matter"). I sketch what such an approach could look like, and why it would
complement but not contradict the view that the material world is the cause of
our experience.Comment: Contribution to the 2018 FQXi essay contest "What is fundamental?
Emergence dâune spĂ©cialitĂ© scientifique dans lâespace - La rĂ©paration de lâADN
International audienceIn the study of science, the specialty is seen as the ideal level of analysis to understand the genesis and development of scientific communities. This article uses bibliometric data to analyze the emergence of DNA repair by testing a hybrid method to identify the specialtyâs appearance in geographical space by focusing on the geographical trajectories of the pioneers in this field. We try to identify the professional mobility of researchers using these bibliometric data, and if possible to highlight the structural networks of places during the emergence stage of the specialty. These networks determine places as much as they are built by individual trajectories. In this way, we try to make a place for the geography of science in the field of social studies of science.Dans lâĂ©tude des sciences, la spĂ©cialitĂ© est perçue comme le niveau dâanalyse idĂ©al pour comprendre la genĂšse et le dĂ©veloppement des collectifs scientifiques. Cet article utilise des donnĂ©es bibliomĂ©triques pour analyser lâĂ©mergence de la RĂ©paration de lâADN en expĂ©rimentant une mĂ©thode mixte pour repĂ©rer son apparition dans lâespace gĂ©ographique. En nous concentrant sur les trajectoires gĂ©ographiques de pionniers dans cedomaine, nous tĂąchons de repĂ©rer leur mobilitĂ© professionnelle Ă lâaide de donnĂ©es bibliomĂ©triques dans la perspective de mettre en Ă©vidence les rĂ©seaux de lieux structurants dans la phase dâĂ©mergence de la spĂ©cialitĂ©. Ces rĂ©seaux de lieux dĂ©terminent autant quâils sont construits par les trajectoires individuelles. Nous essayons ainsi de faire une place Ă la gĂ©ographie des sciences dans le domaine des Ă©tudes sociales des sciences
We favor formal models of heuristics rather than lists of loose dichotomies: a reply to Evans and Over
In their comment on Marewski et al. (good judgments do not require complex cognition, 2009) Evans and Over (heuristic thinking and human intelligence: a commentary on Marewski, Gaissmaier and Gigerenzer, 2009) conjectured that heuristics can often lead to biases and are not error free. This is a most surprising critique. The computational models of heuristics we have tested allow for quantitative predictions of how many errors a given heuristic will make, and we and others have measured the amount of error by analysis, computer simulation, and experiment. This is clear progress over simply giving heuristics labels, such as availability, that do not allow for quantitative comparisons of errors. Evans and Over argue that the reason people rely on heuristics is the accuracy-effort trade-off. However, the comparison between heuristics and more effortful strategies, such as multiple regression, has shown that there are many situations in which a heuristic is more accurate with less effort. Finally, we do not see how the fast and frugal heuristics program could benefit from a dual-process framework unless the dual-process framework is made more precise. Instead, the dual-process framework could benefit if its two âblack boxesâ (Type 1 and Type 2 processes) were substituted by computational models of both heuristics and other processes
- âŠ