399 research outputs found
Quantum Locality?
Robert Griffiths has recently addressed, within the framework of a
'consistent quantum theory' that he has developed, the issue of whether, as is
often claimed, quantum mechanics entails a need for faster-than-light transfers
of information over long distances. He argues that the putative proofs of this
property that involve hidden variables include in their premises some
essentially classical-physics-type assumptions that are fundamentally
incompatible with the precepts of quantum physics. One cannot logically prove
properties of a system by establishing, instead, properties of a system
modified by adding properties alien to the original system. Hence Griffiths'
rejection of hidden-variable-based proofs is logically warranted. Griffiths
mentions the existence of a certain alternative proof that does not involve
hidden variables, and that uses only macroscopically described observable
properties. He notes that he had examined in his book proofs of this general
kind, and concluded that they provide no evidence for nonlocal influences. But
he did not examine the particular proof that he cites. An examination of that
particular proof by the method specified by his 'consistent quantum theory'
shows that the cited proof is valid within that restrictive version of quantum
theory. An added section responds to Griffiths' reply, which cites general
possibilities of ambiguities that make what is to be proved ill-defined, and
hence render the pertinent 'consistent framework' ill defined. But the vagaries
that he cites do not upset the proof in question, which, both by its physical
formulation and by explicit identification, specify the framework to be used.
Griffiths confirms the validity of the proof insofar as that framework is used.
The section also shows, in response to Griffiths' challenge, why a putative
proof of locality that he has described is flawed.Comment: This version adds a response to Griffiths' reply to my original. It
notes that Griffiths confirms the validity of my argument if one uses the
framework that I use. Griffiths' objection that other frameworks exist is not
germaine, because I use the unique one that satisfies the explicitly stated
conditions that the choices be macroscopic choices of experiments and
outcomes in a specified orde
Quantum Electrodynamics at Large Distances II: Nature of the Dominant Singularities
Accurate calculations of macroscopic and mesoscopic properties in quantum
electrodynamics require careful treatment of infrared divergences: standard
treatments introduce spurious large-distances effects. A method for computing
these properties was developed in a companion paper. That method depends upon a
result obtained here about the nature of the singularities that produce the
dominant large-distance behaviour. If all particles in a quantum field theory
have non-zero mass then the Landau-Nakanishi diagrams give strong conditions on
the singularities of the scattering functions. These conditions are severely
weakened in quantum electrodynamics by effects of points where photon momenta
vanish. A new kind of Landau-Nakanishi diagram is developed here. It is geared
specifically to the pole-decomposition functions that dominate the macroscopic
behaviour in quantum electrodynamics, and leads to strong results for these
functions at points where photon momenta vanish.Comment: 40 pages, 11 encapsulated postscript figures, latexed,
math_macros.tex can be found on Archive. full postscript available from
http://theorl.lbl.gov/www/theorgroup/papers/35972.p
Consistent Quantum Counterfactuals
An analysis using classical stochastic processes is used to construct a
consistent system of quantum counterfactual reasoning. When applied to a
counterfactual version of Hardy's paradox, it shows that the probabilistic
character of quantum reasoning together with the ``one framework'' rule
prevents a logical contradiction, and there is no evidence for any mysterious
nonlocal influences. Counterfactual reasoning can support a realistic
interpretation of standard quantum theory (measurements reveal what is actually
there) under appropriate circumstances.Comment: Minor modifications to make it agree with published version. Latex 8
pages, 2 figure
On the Consequences of Retaining the General Validity of Locality in Physical Theory
The empirical validity of the locality (LOC) principle of relativity is used
to argue in favour of a local hidden variable theory (HVT) for individual
quantum processes. It is shown that such a HVT may reproduce the statistical
predictions of quantum mechanics (QM), provided the reproducibility of initial
hidden variable states is limited. This means that in a HVT limits should be
set to the validity of the notion of counterfactual definiteness (CFD). This is
supported by the empirical evidence that past, present, and future are
basically distinct. Our argumentation is contrasted with a recent one by Stapp
resulting in the opposite conclusion, i.e. nonlocality or the existence of
faster-than-light influences. We argue that Stapp's argumentation still depends
in an implicit, but crucial, way on both the notions of hidden variables and of
CFD. In addition, some implications of our results for the debate between Bohr
and Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen are discussed.Comment: revtex, 11 page
On Quantum Jumps, Events and Spontaneous Localization Models
We propose a definite meaning to the concepts of "experiment", "measurement"
and "event" in the event-enhanced formalism of quantum theory. A minimal
piecewise deterministic process is given that can be used for a computer
simulation of real time series of experiments on single quantum objects. As an
example a generalized cloud chamber is described, including multiparticle case.
Relation to the GRW spontaneous localization model is discussed. The second
revised version of the paper contains references to papers by other authors
that are are aiming in the same direction: to enhance quantum theory in such a
way that it will provide stochastic description of events triggered by
individual quantum systems.Comment: 20 page
The quantum speed up as advanced knowledge of the solution
With reference to a search in a database of size N, Grover states: "What is
the reason that one would expect that a quantum mechanical scheme could
accomplish the search in O(square root of N) steps? It would be insightful to
have a simple two line argument for this without having to describe the details
of the search algorithm". The answer provided in this work is: "because any
quantum algorithm takes the time taken by a classical algorithm that knows in
advance 50% of the information that specifies the solution of the problem".
This empirical fact, unnoticed so far, holds for both quadratic and exponential
speed ups and is theoretically justified in three steps: (i) once the physical
representation is extended to the production of the problem on the part of the
oracle and to the final measurement of the computer register, quantum
computation is reduction on the solution of the problem under a relation
representing problem-solution interdependence, (ii) the speed up is explained
by a simple consideration of time symmetry, it is the gain of information about
the solution due to backdating, to before running the algorithm, a
time-symmetric part of the reduction on the solution; this advanced knowledge
of the solution reduces the size of the solution space to be explored by the
algorithm, (iii) if I is the information acquired by measuring the content of
the computer register at the end of the algorithm, the quantum algorithm takes
the time taken by a classical algorithm that knows in advance 50% of I, which
brings us to the initial statement.Comment: 23 pages, to be published in IJT
Free Will in a Quantum World?
In this paper, I argue that Conway and Kochen’s Free Will Theorem (1,2) to the conclusion that quantum mechanics and relativity entail freedom for the particles, does not change the situation in favor of a libertarian position as they would like. In fact, the theorem more or less implicitly assumes that people are free, and thus it begs the question. Moreover, it does not prove neither that if people are free, so are particles, nor that the property people possess when they are said to be free is the same as the one particles possess when they are claimed to be free. I then analyze the Free State Theorem (2), which generalizes the Free Will Theorem without the assumption that people are free, and I show that it does not prove anything about free will, since the notion of freedom for particles is either inconsistent, or it does not concern our common understanding of freedom. In both cases, the Free Will Theorem and the Free State Theorem do not provide any enlightenment on the constraints physics can pose on free will
Minimum detection efficiency for a loophole-free atom-photon Bell experiment
In Bell experiments, one problem is to achieve high enough photodetection to
ensure that there is no possibility of describing the results via a local
hidden-variable model. Using the Clauser-Horne inequality and a two-photon
non-maximally entangled state, a photodetection efficiency higher than 0.67 is
necessary. Here we discuss atom-photon Bell experiments. We show that, assuming
perfect detection efficiency of the atom, it is possible to perform a
loophole-free atom-photon Bell experiment whenever the photodetection
efficiency exceeds 0.50.Comment: REVTeX4, 4 pages, 1 figur
Lorentz-covariant quantum mechanics and preferred frame
In this paper the relativistic quantum mechanics is considered in the
framework of the nonstandard synchronization scheme for clocks. Such a
synchronization preserves Poincar{\'e} covariance but (at least formally)
distinguishes an inertial frame. This enables to avoid the problem of a
noncausal transmision of information related to breaking of the Bell's
inequalities in QM. Our analysis has been focused mainly on the problem of
existence of a proper position operator for massive particles. We have proved
that in our framework such an operator exists for particles with arbitrary
spin. It fulfills all the requirements: it is Hermitean and covariant, it has
commuting components and moreover its eigenvectors (localised states) are also
covariant. We have found the explicit form of the position operator and have
demonstrated that in the preferred frame our operator coincides with the
Newton--Wigner one. We have also defined a covariant spin operator and have
constructed an invariant spin square operator. Moreover, full algebra of
observables consisting of position operators, fourmomentum operators and spin
operators is manifestly Poincar\'e covariant in this framework. Our results
support expectations of other authors (Bell, Eberhard) that a consistent
formulation of quantum mechanics demands existence of a preferred frame.Comment: 21 pages, LaTeX file, no figure
The importance of quantum decoherence in brain processes
Based on a calculation of neural decoherence rates, we argue that that the
degrees of freedom of the human brain that relate to cognitive processes should
be thought of as a classical rather than quantum system, i.e., that there is
nothing fundamentally wrong with the current classical approach to neural
network simulations. We find that the decoherence timescales ~10^{-13}-10^{-20}
seconds are typically much shorter than the relevant dynamical timescales
(~0.001-0.1 seconds), both for regular neuron firing and for kink-like
polarization excitations in microtubules. This conclusion disagrees with
suggestions by Penrose and others that the brain acts as a quantum computer,
and that quantum coherence is related to consciousness in a fundamental way.Comment: Minor changes to match accepted PRE version. 15 pages with 5 figs
included. Color figures and links at
http://www.physics.upenn.edu/~max/brain.html or from [email protected].
Physical Review E, in pres
- …