207 research outputs found

    Reichenbach's Common Cause Principle in Algebraic Quantum Field Theory with Locally Finite Degrees of Freedom

    Full text link
    In the paper it will be shown that Reichenbach's Weak Common Cause Principle is not valid in algebraic quantum field theory with locally finite degrees of freedom in general. Namely, for any pair of projections A and B supported in spacelike separated double cones O(a) and O(b), respectively, a correlating state can be given for which there is no nontrivial common cause (system) located in the union of the backward light cones of O(a) and O(b) and commuting with the both A and B. Since noncommuting common cause solutions are presented in these states the abandonment of commutativity can modulate this result: noncommutative Common Cause Principles might survive in these models

    Local Operations and Completely Positive Maps in Algebraic Quantum Field Theory

    Full text link
    Einstein introduced the locality principle which states that all physical effect in some finite space-time region does not influence its space-like separated finite region. Recently, in algebraic quantum field theory, R\'{e}dei captured the idea of the locality principle by the notion of operational separability. The operation in operational separability is performed in some finite space-time region, and leaves unchanged the state in its space-like separated finite space-time region. This operation is defined with a completely positive map. In the present paper, we justify using a completely positive map as a local operation in algebraic quantum field theory, and show that this local operation can be approximately written with Kraus operators under the funnel property

    Remarks on Causality in Relativistic Quantum Field Theory

    Get PDF
    It is shown that the correlations predicted by relativistic quantum field theory in locally normal states between projections in local von Neumann algebras \cA(V_1),\cA(V_2) associated with spacelike separated spacetime regions V1,V2V_1,V_2 have a (Reichenbachian) common cause located in the union of the backward light cones of V1V_1 and V2V_2. Further comments on causality and independence in quantum field theory are made.Comment: 10 pages, Latex, Quantum Structures 2002 Conference Proceedings submission. Minor revision of the order of definitions on p.

    Noncommutative causality in algebraic quantum field theory

    Get PDF
    In the paper it will be argued that embracing noncommuting common causes in the causal explanation of quantum correlations in algebraic quantum field theory has the following two beneficial consequences: it helps (i) to maintain the validity of Reichenbach's Common Causal Principle and (ii) to provide a local common causal explanation for a set of correlations violating the Bell inequality

    A portrait of Lewis John Stadler 1896-1954

    Get PDF
    G. P. REDEI, UNIVERSITY OF MISSOURI, COLUMBIA, MISSOURI

    Applying causality principles to the axiomatization of probabilistic cellular automata

    Full text link
    Cellular automata (CA) consist of an array of identical cells, each of which may take one of a finite number of possible states. The entire array evolves in discrete time steps by iterating a global evolution G. Further, this global evolution G is required to be shift-invariant (it acts the same everywhere) and causal (information cannot be transmitted faster than some fixed number of cells per time step). At least in the classical, reversible and quantum cases, these two top-down axiomatic conditions are sufficient to entail more bottom-up, operational descriptions of G. We investigate whether the same is true in the probabilistic case. Keywords: Characterization, noise, Markov process, stochastic Einstein locality, screening-off, common cause principle, non-signalling, Multi-party non-local box.Comment: 13 pages, 6 figures, LaTeX, v2: refs adde

    Flower differentiation in arabidopsis

    Get PDF
    There is a consensus among developmental geneticists that few generalizations are possible at the present status of the field, and even the boundaries are difficult to define. Yet in few special cases, consistent facts have been accumulated which point to systems of controls of differentiation.In the facultative long-day plant Arabidopsis, the differentiation of flower primordia is controlled by several gene loci. Recessive mutations may determine in a qualitatively distinct manner the onset of flower development. Continuous illumination in contrast to 8-9 hours daily cycles of light promotes flowering in all genotypes. Mutants at the ld locus are incapable of flowering under short days and entail a critical day-length. Different alleles at the gi locus require several times as long period for flower induction than the wild type under 24 hours light yet under short days they do not differ, very conspicuously from the standard type. Mutants at the co locus are late flowering and recessive under long days but they are more precocious than the wild type under short days and they display dominance. In total darkness, the wild type and all mutants flower early. The aseptic feeding of 5-bromodeoxyuridine highly accelerates flower differentiation in all genotypes under long days and also under short days with the exception of the ld mutants. The analog is incorporated into the DNA of all types. Bromodeoxyuridine-grown plants accumulate higher amounts of radioactivity, provided by 14[subscript C]-amino acids, into a chromatin fraction. The experimental observations support the view that flowering in this plant is under negative control and bromodeoxyuridineis hampering the synthesis of a postulated suppressor.G. P. REDEI, GREGORIA ACEDO AND G. GAVAZZI, University of Missouri, Columbia, Mo

    Extended Representations of Observables and States for a Noncontextual Reinterpretation of QM

    Full text link
    A crucial and problematical feature of quantum mechanics (QM) is nonobjectivity of properties. The ESR model restores objectivity reinterpreting quantum probabilities as conditional on detection and embodying the mathematical formalism of QM into a broader noncontextual (hence local) framework. We propose here an improved presentation of the ESR model containing a more complete mathematical representation of the basic entities of the model. We also extend the model to mixtures showing that the mathematical representations of proper mixtures does not coincide with the mathematical representation of mixtures provided by QM, while the representation of improper mixtures does. This feature of the ESR model entails that some interpretative problems raising in QM when dealing with mixtures are avoided. From an empirical point of view the predictions of the ESR model depend on some parameters which may be such that they are very close to the predictions of QM in most cases. But the nonstandard representation of proper mixtures allows us to propose the scheme of an experiment that could check whether the predictions of QM or the predictions of the ESR model are correct.Comment: 17 pages, standard latex. Extensively revised versio

    Algebras of Measurements: the logical structure of Quantum Mechanics

    Full text link
    In Quantum Physics, a measurement is represented by a projection on some closed subspace of a Hilbert space. We study algebras of operators that abstract from the algebra of projections on closed subspaces of a Hilbert space. The properties of such operators are justified on epistemological grounds. Commutation of measurements is a central topic of interest. Classical logical systems may be viewed as measurement algebras in which all measurements commute. Keywords: Quantum measurements, Measurement algebras, Quantum Logic. PACS: 02.10.-v.Comment: Submitted, 30 page

    Extending structures I: the level of groups

    Full text link
    Let HH be a group and EE a set such that H⊆EH \subseteq E. We shall describe and classify up to an isomorphism of groups that stabilizes HH the set of all group structures that can be defined on EE such that HH is a subgroup of EE. A general product, which we call the unified product, is constructed such that both the crossed product and the bicrossed product of two groups are special cases of it. It is associated to HH and to a system ((S,1S,∗),◃, â–č, f)\bigl((S, 1_S,\ast), \triangleleft, \, \triangleright, \, f \bigl) called a group extending structure and we denote it by H⋉SH \ltimes S. There exists a group structure on EE containing HH as a subgroup if and only if there exists an isomorphism of groups (E,⋅)≅H⋉S(E, \cdot) \cong H \ltimes S, for some group extending structure ((S,1S,∗),◃, â–č, f)\bigl((S, 1_S,\ast), \triangleleft, \, \triangleright, \, f \bigl). All such group structures on EE are classified up to an isomorphism of groups that stabilizes HH by a cohomological type set K⋉2(H,(S,1S)){\mathcal K}^{2}_{\ltimes} (H, (S, 1_S)). A Schreier type theorem is proved and an explicit example is given: it classifies up to an isomorphism that stabilizes HH all groups that contain HH as a subgroup of index 2.Comment: 17 pages; to appear in Algebras and Representation Theor
    • 

    corecore