17 research outputs found

    Repudiating Morals Legislation: Rendering the Constitutional Right to Privacy Obsolete

    Get PDF
    This article is set out in three parts. Part II outlines the difficulties with the right to privacy. Part III articulates the relationship between morals legislation and privacy, demonstrating that we no longer need the latter as long as the state eschews the former. Part IV argues that the Court in Lawrence articulates a new standard of rational review where specific appeal to morality is constitutionally suspect, allowing us to reject the right to privac

    Repudiating Morals Legislation: Rendering the Constitutional Right to Privacy Obsolete

    Get PDF
    This article is set out in three parts. Part II outlines the difficulties with the right to privacy. Part III articulates the relationship between morals legislation and privacy, demonstrating that we no longer need the latter as long as the state eschews the former. Part IV argues that the Court in Lawrence articulates a new standard of rational review where specific appeal to morality is constitutionally suspect, allowing us to reject the right to privac

    Collapsing Suspect Class with Suspect Classification: Why Strict Scrutiny is Too Strict and Maybe Not Strict Enough

    Full text link
    While scholarly work often analyzes the nature and scopeof the Court\u27s tiers of scrutiny approach to enforcingequality, this Article examines the underlying theory ofequal protection. This Article mounts a challenge to thetheory of higher scrutiny, and, in particular,strict scrutiny.It seeks to analyze two questions: (1) What principles triggerheightened scrutiny? and (2) Why does the Court need tosubject laws that discriminate on the basis of race to strictscrutiny? The first question concerns the underlying theoryof equal protection doctrine: the what of higher scrutiny.Scholarly work that seeks to answer this question rightlydistinguishes between principles of antidifferentiation andantisubordination, principles that underlie the Court\u27sthreshold decision to impose higher scrutiny. Yet this lineof reasoning fails to realize that the Court endorses neither.By collapsing a suspect class analysis-a focus on anti-subordination-with a suspect classification one--a focuson anti-differentiation, the Court\u27s jurisprudence pervertsboth. It points to an inconsistent theory of reviewinglegislation. This is a novel critique of equal protectiondoctrine, one that has hithertogone unnoticed.The second question concerns the purpose or goal of strictscrutiny: the why of such scrutiny. Once we have decidedthat strict scrutiny is necessary, what is it meant toaccomplish? Here this Article focuses only on the doctrineof strict scrutiny. Drawing from case law and John Ely\u27sclassic defense of judicial review, it argues that the answerto the why question is about either remedying democraticdefects of representation or distinguishing between benignpurposes on one hand and racist or nefarious ones on theother. If this is the why of strict scrutiny, it turns out to be both too strict and not strict enough. While scholars rightlycriticize the Court for failing to deploy strict scrutiny incertain cases, namely those where unconscious racism maybe afoot, they do not home in on the cost in deploying it.This Article argues that strict scrutiny is too strict, becauseit invalidates a wide range of laws that seek to better thestatus of racial minorities. Framing Justice Harlan\u27sdissent in Plessy v. Ferguson (1896) in a novel light, itargues that a rational review analysis is sufficient to do thedistinguishing work in cases where a law faciallydiscriminates on the basis of race. This Article draws fromthe recent decision by the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals inPerry v. Brown (9th Cir. 2012) invalidingProposition8, theCalifornia constitutional amendment defining marriagebetween a man and a woman, to buttress this claim of thesufficiency of a rational review analysis. After all, if such areview can invalidate legislation based on homophobia,mere hostility to gays and lesbians, it can invalidatelegislation based on racism, mere hostility to racialminorities. This Article concludes that strict scrutiny, as itis currently understood, is too blunt an instrument. Wemust be careful in deploying it, precisely because it standsat the center of our dual commitments to democracy andjudicial review

    Beyond the conflict: religion in the public sphere and deliberative democracy

    Get PDF
    Traditionally, liberals have confined religion to the sphere of the ‘private’ or ‘non-political’. However, recent debates over the use of religious symbols in public spaces, state financing of faith schools, and tax relief for religious organisations suggest that this distinction is not particularly useful in easing the tension between liberal ideas of equality among citizens and freedom of religion. This article deals with one aspect of this debate, which concerns whether members of religious communities should receive exemptions from regulations that place a distinctively heavy burden on them. For supporters of exemptions, protection for diverse practices and religious beliefs justifies such a special treatment. For others, this is a form of positive discrimination incompatible with equal citizenship. Drawing on Habermas’ understanding of churches as ‘communities of interpretation’ this article explores possible alternative solutions to both the ‘rule-andexemption’ approach and the ‘neutralist’ approach. Our proposal rests on the idea of mutual learning between secular and religious perspectives. On this interpretation, what is required is, firstly, generation and maintenance of public spaces in which there could be discussion and dialogue about particular cases, and, secondly, evaluation of whether the basic conditions of moral discourse are present in these spaces. Thus deliberation becomes a touchstone for the building of a shared democratic etho

    Global, regional, and national burden of disorders affecting the nervous system, 1990–2021: a systematic analysis for the Global Burden of Disease Study 2021

    Get PDF
    BackgroundDisorders affecting the nervous system are diverse and include neurodevelopmental disorders, late-life neurodegeneration, and newly emergent conditions, such as cognitive impairment following COVID-19. Previous publications from the Global Burden of Disease, Injuries, and Risk Factor Study estimated the burden of 15 neurological conditions in 2015 and 2016, but these analyses did not include neurodevelopmental disorders, as defined by the International Classification of Diseases (ICD)-11, or a subset of cases of congenital, neonatal, and infectious conditions that cause neurological damage. Here, we estimate nervous system health loss caused by 37 unique conditions and their associated risk factors globally, regionally, and nationally from 1990 to 2021.MethodsWe estimated mortality, prevalence, years lived with disability (YLDs), years of life lost (YLLs), and disability-adjusted life-years (DALYs), with corresponding 95% uncertainty intervals (UIs), by age and sex in 204 countries and territories, from 1990 to 2021. We included morbidity and deaths due to neurological conditions, for which health loss is directly due to damage to the CNS or peripheral nervous system. We also isolated neurological health loss from conditions for which nervous system morbidity is a consequence, but not the primary feature, including a subset of congenital conditions (ie, chromosomal anomalies and congenital birth defects), neonatal conditions (ie, jaundice, preterm birth, and sepsis), infectious diseases (ie, COVID-19, cystic echinococcosis, malaria, syphilis, and Zika virus disease), and diabetic neuropathy. By conducting a sequela-level analysis of the health outcomes for these conditions, only cases where nervous system damage occurred were included, and YLDs were recalculated to isolate the non-fatal burden directly attributable to nervous system health loss. A comorbidity correction was used to calculate total prevalence of all conditions that affect the nervous system combined.FindingsGlobally, the 37 conditions affecting the nervous system were collectively ranked as the leading group cause of DALYs in 2021 (443 million, 95% UI 378–521), affecting 3·40 billion (3·20–3·62) individuals (43·1%, 40·5–45·9 of the global population); global DALY counts attributed to these conditions increased by 18·2% (8·7–26·7) between 1990 and 2021. Age-standardised rates of deaths per 100 000 people attributed to these conditions decreased from 1990 to 2021 by 33·6% (27·6–38·8), and age-standardised rates of DALYs attributed to these conditions decreased by 27·0% (21·5–32·4). Age-standardised prevalence was almost stable, with a change of 1·5% (0·7–2·4). The ten conditions with the highest age-standardised DALYs in 2021 were stroke, neonatal encephalopathy, migraine, Alzheimer's disease and other dementias, diabetic neuropathy, meningitis, epilepsy, neurological complications due to preterm birth, autism spectrum disorder, and nervous system cancer.InterpretationAs the leading cause of overall disease burden in the world, with increasing global DALY counts, effective prevention, treatment, and rehabilitation strategies for disorders affecting the nervous system are needed

    An Illiberal Union

    No full text
    This Article breaks new ground by applying the philosophical framework of liberal neutrality (most famously articulated by John Rawls) to the United States Supreme Court’s jurisprudence on marriage. At first blush, the Court’s decision in Obergefell v. Hodges—the culmination of marriage rights—seems to affirm a central principle of liberalism, namely equal access to marriage regardless of sexual orientation. Gays and lesbians can finally take part in an institution that celebrates the union of two committed individuals. But perversely, in its attempt to expand access to marriage, the Court has simultaneously entrenched values that are antithetical to the basic tenants of liberal neutrality. Working at the nexus of political theory and constitutional law, this Article provides the first critique of marriage as an illiberal union. It focuses on three problems with the current state of marriage: one, marriage is problematically a spiritual—not secular—status, affirming an intangible quality that threatens the separation of church and state; two, in marrying couples, the state stigmatizes those who choose not to marry; and three, by promoting monogamy, marriage unreasonably excludes alternative adult relationships and even permits the state to criminalize certain kinds of sexual activity. By questioning the legitimacy of the institution itself, this Article breaks from the usual focus on the issue of access. It ultimately suggests a radical rethinking of the relationship between marriage and the state’s role in regulating it, where marriage becomes a private contract rather than a state-sanctioned, civil institution

    Collapsing Suspect Class with Suspect Classification: Why Strict Scrutiny is Too Strict and Maybe Not Strict Enough

    No full text
    While scholarly work often analyzes the nature and scopeof the Court\u27s tiers of scrutiny approach to enforcingequality, this Article examines the underlying theory ofequal protection. This Article mounts a challenge to thetheory of higher scrutiny, and, in particular,strict scrutiny.It seeks to analyze two questions: (1) What principles triggerheightened scrutiny? and (2) Why does the Court need tosubject laws that discriminate on the basis of race to strictscrutiny? The first question concerns the underlying theoryof equal protection doctrine: the what of higher scrutiny.Scholarly work that seeks to answer this question rightlydistinguishes between principles of antidifferentiation andantisubordination, principles that underlie the Court\u27sthreshold decision to impose higher scrutiny. Yet this lineof reasoning fails to realize that the Court endorses neither.By collapsing a suspect class analysis-a focus on anti-subordination-with a suspect classification one--a focuson anti-differentiation, the Court\u27s jurisprudence pervertsboth. It points to an inconsistent theory of reviewinglegislation. This is a novel critique of equal protectiondoctrine, one that has hithertogone unnoticed.The second question concerns the purpose or goal of strictscrutiny: the why of such scrutiny. Once we have decidedthat strict scrutiny is necessary, what is it meant toaccomplish? Here this Article focuses only on the doctrineof strict scrutiny. Drawing from case law and John Ely\u27sclassic defense of judicial review, it argues that the answerto the why question is about either remedying democraticdefects of representation or distinguishing between benignpurposes on one hand and racist or nefarious ones on theother. If this is the why of strict scrutiny, it turns out to be both too strict and not strict enough. While scholars rightlycriticize the Court for failing to deploy strict scrutiny incertain cases, namely those where unconscious racism maybe afoot, they do not home in on the cost in deploying it.This Article argues that strict scrutiny is too strict, becauseit invalidates a wide range of laws that seek to better thestatus of racial minorities. Framing Justice Harlan\u27sdissent in Plessy v. Ferguson (1896) in a novel light, itargues that a rational review analysis is sufficient to do thedistinguishing work in cases where a law faciallydiscriminates on the basis of race. This Article draws fromthe recent decision by the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals inPerry v. Brown (9th Cir. 2012) invalidingProposition8, theCalifornia constitutional amendment defining marriagebetween a man and a woman, to buttress this claim of thesufficiency of a rational review analysis. After all, if such areview can invalidate legislation based on homophobia,mere hostility to gays and lesbians, it can invalidatelegislation based on racism, mere hostility to racialminorities. This Article concludes that strict scrutiny, as itis currently understood, is too blunt an instrument. Wemust be careful in deploying it, precisely because it standsat the center of our dual commitments to democracy andjudicial review
    corecore