45 research outputs found

    Early Childhood Science and Engineering: Engaging Platforms for Fostering Domain-General Learning Skills

    Get PDF
    Early childhood science and engineering education offer a prime context to foster approaches-to-learning (ATL) and executive functioning (EF) by eliciting children’s natural curiosity about the world, providing a unique opportunity to engage children in hands-on learning experiences that promote critical thinking, problem solving, collaboration, persistence, and other adaptive domain-general learning skills. Indeed, in any science experiment or engineering problem, children make observations, engage in collaborative conversations with teachers and peers, and think flexibly to come up with predictions or potential solutions to their problem. Inherent to science and engineering is the idea that one learns from initial failures within an iterative trial-and-error process where children practice risk-taking, persistence, tolerance for frustration, and sustaining focus. Unfortunately, science and engineering instruction is typically absent from early childhood classrooms, and particularly so in programs that serve children from low-income families. However, our early science and engineering intervention research shows teachers how to build science and engineering instruction into activities that are already happening in their classrooms, which boosts their confidence and removes some of the stigma around science and engineering. In this paper, we discuss the promise of research that uses early childhood science and engineering experiences as engaging, hands-on, interactive platforms to instill ATL and EF in young children living below the poverty line. We propose that early childhood science and engineering offer a central theme that captures children’s attention and allows for integrated instruction across domain-general (ATL, EF, and social–emotional) and domain-specific (e.g., language, literacy, mathematics, and science) content, allowing for contextualized experiences that make learning more meaningful and captivating for children

    G. Bligh, Les bases philosophiques du positivisme juridique de H.L.A. Hart (Varenne, 2017)

    No full text
    International audienc

    H.L.A. Hart’s Pluralist Penal Philosophy

    No full text
    Cette thĂšse porte sur la philosophie pĂ©nale de Herbert Hart, c’est-Ă -dire sur ses rĂ©flexions au sujet de la dĂ©finition de la peine, de la justification de la peine, de la responsabilitĂ© pĂ©nale et de la dĂ©termination de la peine en qualitĂ© et en quantitĂ©. Nous soutenons que Hart ne dĂ©fend ni une thĂ©orie mixte de la peine, ni une forme d’utilitarisme de la rĂšgle, ni une forme d’utilitarisme libĂ©ral, ni une approche goal / constraint. Son approche est pluraliste. En effet, son pluralisme des valeurs, trĂšs proche de celui d’Isaiah Berlin, lui permet de rĂ©soudre la tension entre la justification utilitariste de la peine et certains principes de justice concernant la responsabilitĂ© pĂ©nale (par exemple, ne pas punir ceux qui n’auraient pas pu agir autrement) et la dĂ©termination de la peine (par exemple, ne pas infliger des peines disproportionnĂ©es). Par ailleurs, son pluralisme des formes de raison morale lui permet d’admettre une pluralitĂ© de justifications de la peine qui ne sont pas du mĂȘme type (la justification utilitariste, celle fondĂ©e sur le droit spĂ©cial a l’obĂ©issance des dĂ©sobĂ©issants, celle fondĂ©e sur le droit gĂ©nĂ©ral a un niveau raisonnable de sĂ©curitĂ©) et d’expliquer comment la commission d’une infraction peut en elle-mĂȘme justifier l’infliction d’une sanction. Tout au long de cette thĂšse, nous analysons les rapports complexes entre Hart et la tradition utilitariste (en particulier Bentham et Mill). MĂȘme si Hart a indĂ©niablement une dette envers l’utilitarisme, il ne cesse de critiquer son monisme et la tentative de fonder l’ensemble de nos convictions morales bien pesĂ©es sur le principe d’utilitĂ©. En outre, nous essayons de montrer que la philosophie du langage ordinaire a eu une influence non nĂ©gligeable sur sa philosophie pĂ©nale, mĂȘme si cette influence est moins visible que dans sa thĂ©orie gĂ©nĂ©rale du droit. Enfin, nous accordons une attention particuliĂšre au dĂ©bat Hart/Wootton dont les enjeux ont Ă©tĂ© sous-estimĂ©s : la question du choix entre un systĂšme pĂ©nal base sur des peines et un systĂšme prĂ©ventif base sur des mesures, selon nous, reste ouverte. Cette thĂšse ne vise pas uniquement Ă  corriger les mauvaises interprĂ©tations de la philosophie pĂ©nale de Hart. Elle cherche Ă©galement Ă  approfondir les idĂ©es qu’il a seulement esquissĂ©es, Ă  clarifier les principes qu’il a dĂ©fendus, Ă  mettre en Ă©vidence les points faibles de sa pensĂ©e et Ă  mettre de l’ordre dans ses rĂ©flexions. En ce sens, elle est autant la lecture d’une Ɠuvre qu’un dialogue avec celle-ci.This dissertation focuses on Herbert Hart’s penal philosophy, i.e. his thoughts on the definition of punishment, justification of punishment, criminal responsibility, and sentencing. We argue that Hart defends neither a mixed theory of punishment, nor a form of rule-utilitarianism, nor a form of liberal utilitarianism, nor a goal/constraint approach. His approach is pluralist. Indeed, his value pluralism, very close to that of Isaiah Berlin, allows him to resolve the tension between the utilitarian justification of punishment and certain principles of justice concerning criminal responsibility (e.g. not punishing those who could not have acted otherwise) and sentencing (e.g. not inflicting disproportionate punishments). In addition, his pluralism about forms of moral reason enables him to admit a plurality of justifications of punishment that are not of the same type (the utilitarian justification, that based on the special right to the obedience of disobedient persons, that based on the general right to a reasonable level of security) and to explain how the commission of an offence may in itself justify the imposition of a sanction. Throughout this dissertation, we analyse the complex relationship between Hart and the utilitarian tradition (particularly Bentham and Mill). Although Hart undeniably owes a debt to utilitarianism, he is a constant critic of its monism and the attempt to base all of our considered moral convictions on the principle of utility. Moreover, we try to show that ordinary language philosophy has had a significant influence on his penal philosophy, even if this influence is less visible than in his jurisprudence. Finally, we pay particular attention to the Hart/Wootton debate, the stakes of which have been underestimated: the question of the choice between a penal system based on punishment and a preventive system based on measures, in our view, remains open. This dissertation is not only intended to correct the misinterpretations of Hart’s penal philosophy. It also seeks to deepen the ideas he only sketched out, to clarify the principles he defended, to highlight the weaknesses in his thinking, to put his thoughts in order. In this sense, it as much the reading of a work as a dialogue with it

    Drug Courts and the “responsibility without blame” approach

    No full text
    International audienceThis paper starts from a paradox and aims to solve it. On the one hand, although Drug Courts (DCs) are one of the most interesting penal innovations in recent years, running counter to the dominant retributive approach and the rival approach based on deterrence, they have surprisingly not attracted the attention of philosophers and therefore lack a solid philosophical foundation. On the other hand, although Pickard’s “responsibility without blame” approach looks very convincing on paper, its practical applications remain unclear outside the clinical context. I argue that Pickard’s approach is the theoretical framework that DCs need and that they are a compelling application of it: DCs do ascribe to participants various forms of responsibility (criminal “liability-responsibility”, responsibility of choice, responsibility for progress or failure, responsibility as answerability, tort liability) while striving to keep “affective blame” at bay in order to help them regain their autonomy. However, I argue that some of the limitations of both this approach and DCs become apparent once we consider the “outer limits” of DCs, in other words those who are terminated from DCs and those who refuse to enter DCs in the first place

    The Varieties of Attitudes Towards Offenders

    No full text
    International audienceI argue that penal philosophy should focus more on our attitudes towards offenders, since these attitudes can shed new light on theories or principles of punishment (of which they are often expressions) and also play a significant role in changing the face of criminal justice. Building on Strawson’s “Freedom and Resentment,” I define attitudes as certain ways of seeing human beings that logically include or exclude various emotional, behavioral, and linguistic responses, that can be more or less natural, and over which we have some degree of voluntary control. I argue that, understood in this sense, there are broadly speaking six attitudes towards offenders: the retributive, the hostile, the moralistic, the paternalistic, the merciful, and the actuarial. After presenting each of these attitudes, I sum up my analysis by focusing on the Polanski sexual abuse case. I then introduce the concept of second-order attitudes, where egalitarianism is the attitude that consists of taking the same attitude towards all offenders, and particularism is the attitude that consists of adjusting your attitude to each offender. Finally, I briefly explain why a mix of the retributive and the merciful should be our default attitude

    Faut-il mĂ©riter de souffrir pour ĂȘtre puni ? Parfit et la sanction pĂ©nale

    No full text
    International audienc
    corecore