29 research outputs found

    The normative decision theory in economics : a philosophy of science perspective: The case of the expected utility theory

    Get PDF
    This article analyses how normative decision theory is understood by economists. The paradigmatic example of normative decision theory, discussed in the article, is the expected utility theory. It has been suggested that the status of the expected utility theory has been ambiguous since early in its history. The theory has been treated as descriptive, normative, or both. This observation is the starting point for the analysis presented here. The text discusses various ways in which economists and philosophers of economics have conceptualized the normative status of the expected utility theory, and it shows that none is satisfactory from the point of view of philosophy of science.Peer reviewe

    How behavioural research has informed consumer law : The many faces of behavioural research

    Get PDF
    In this chapter we outline a history of various strands of behavioural research pertaining to consumer behaviour. We first look at the current field of consumer behaviour research qua a sub-discipline of marketing. This discussion reveals the multi-disciplinary nature of the field, which turns us next to the history of general trends in psychology that exert influences on many disciplines, and then to more specific developments in behavioural research at the intersection of economics and psychology. In the last section we review how these strands of behavioural research have been taken up by legal scholars at various points in history.Peer reviewe

    Review of Mariana Mazzucato’s 'The value of everything: making and taking in the global economy'

    Get PDF
    Book review. Reviewed work: The Value of Everything: Making and Taking in the Global Economy / Mariana Mazzucato. - New York : Public Affairs, 2018, 384 pages, ISBN 978-161039675-2.Non peer reviewe

    Posner versus Kelsen : the challenges for scientific analysis of law

    Get PDF
    Law & economics scholars claim, among other things, to provide explanations of how law impacts behaviour. The aim of this article is to shed light on the conceptual and methodological difficulties related to analysis of the impact that law has on behaviour. The analysis advanced in the paper takes as its starting point a commentary on Richard Posner's interpretation of Hans Kelsen's pure theory of law. The work of Kelsen is treated as a meta-theoretical analysis that reveals some of the presumptions of theoretical approaches to law that claim to be scientific and, in particular, that claim to scientifically analyse the law's influence on behaviour. The article concludes with a methodological proposal on how to approach the identified methodological challenges and conceptual tensions that law & economics contends with.Peer reviewe

    Introduction to symposium

    Get PDF
    This symposium on behavioural economics features some of the papers that were presented during the workshop Economics and/or Psychology? Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Behavioural Economics, which we organised at the University of Helsinki in May 2017. The frame and focus of the workshop were developed in 2015 and 2016 in a reading group on behavioural economics at TINT – Centre for Philosophy of Social Science. The workshop attracted not only speakers from all over the world, but also many people who flew to Helsinki just to listen to the presentations and discuss the past, present, and future of behavioural economics. Readers can find more information about the event in a detailed report written by our colleague Chiara Lisciandra (2017 Lisciandra, C. (2017). Interdisciplinary perspectives on behavioral economics, 22–23 May. The Reasoner, 11(7), 43–44. Retrieved from https://blogs.kent.ac.uk/thereasoner/files/2017/06/TheReasoner-117.pdf [Google Scholar] ). The workshop was an attempt to stimulate reflection on the current state of the art in behavioural economics from the perspectives of history and philosophy of science, economic methodology, history of economic thought, science and technology studies, sociology of science, and science policy, as well as from the point of view of self-identified behavioural economists. In the call for papers we asked: Is it possible to define behavioural economics by a set of theoretical or methodological commitments? Is behavioural economics a truly interdisciplinary endeavour, or rather just a minor modification of the so-called neoclassical economics? What is the interplay between the epistemic and the institutional dimensions in the development of interdisciplinary exchanges between economics and other disciplines? We were also interested in investigating factors that contributed to the academic and policy success of behavioural economics; in particular why has the so-called ‘new’ behavioural economics become the mainstream, whereas alternative approaches to integrating psychological insights with economics have not? After two days of our collective effort to address these questions, it became clear that what we call the received view on behavioural economics needs revisions in several ways. What does the received view consist of? In a nutshell, it states that behavioural economics is a research programme that is (i) alternative to neoclassical economics, that develops (ii) more psychologically realistic models of economic decision-making (iii) based on evidence, mostly coming from the laboratory experiments. It is also widely believed that these features allow behavioural economists to design better, more evidence-based, policies. In what follows, we summarise how the papers presented in this symposium issue complicate the received view or cast doubts on its plausibility. First of all, Vladimir and Avtonomov’s analysis situates the alleged alternative nature of behavioural economics in an historical context, arguing that the debates around behavioural economics closely follow the established pattern of Methodenstreits in the history of economics. In this sense, behavioural economics is one of a number of ‘behavioural shifts’ that keep redefining dominant modes of analysis in economics. Erik Angner, however, insists that some practitioners mischaracterise this as an assimilation of behavioural economics into neoclassical models. The nature of the synthesis, Angner argues, was the opposite, making everyone behavioural economists now. Second, the claim that behavioural economics is a more realistic approach to the study of economic behaviour is challenged from a range of perspectives. James Grayot and Michael Joffe argue that it is not clear in which sense behavioural economics is based on psychological findings. Sabine Frerichs argues that the way in which most behavioural economists attempt to integrate ‘the social’ into their models is in fact very limited and reductive in failing to acknowledge the social contingency of behaviour. More generally, behavioural economists’ view of agency – humans as opposed to econs – is criticised as too simplistic to capture its internal and social complexity, such as multiple agents (James Grayot) and gender roles (Giandomenica Becchio). Finally, concerning the view that behavioural economics is empirical and evidence-based, Joffe suggests a viable alternative to the way mainstream behavioural economists model causal mechanisms based on available empirical findings. O. Çağlar Dede looks at policies inspired by the rise of behavioural economics and shows that the ‘behavioural insights’ are not enough to propose and evaluate evidence-based policy: we need a plurality of scientific findings. We hope that this symposium will contribute to the enrichment of the received view, by encouraging researchers, including both analysts and practitioners of behavioural economics, to envision and implement different ways of developing this intriguing field.Non peer reviewe

    The ethics of behavioural public policy

    Get PDF
    Non peer reviewe
    corecore