91 research outputs found
Does Pyrrhonism Have Practical or Epistemic Value?
My purpose in this paper is to examine whether Pyrrhonian skepticism, as this stance is described in Sextus Empiricusâs extant works, has practical or epistemic value. More precisely, I would like to consider whether the Pyrrhonistâs suspension of judgment (áŒÏÎżÏÎź) and undisturbedness (áŒÏαÏÎ±ÎŸÎŻÎ±) can be deemed to be of practical or epistemic value. By âpracticalâ value I mean both moral value and prudential value. Moral value refers to moral rightness and wrongness; prudential value to the value of well-being, personal or social. Hence, when I ask whether the Pyrrhonistâs suspension and undisturbedness have practical value, I mean whether they make us behave in a manner that is morally right or wrong, and whether they allow us to attain those goals that would make it possible to live well. As for âepistemicâ value, it refers basically to the values of attaining truth and avoiding error. Hence, when I ask whether the Pyrrhonistâs suspension has epistemic value, I mean whether it allows us to attain truth and avoid error. My main focus will be the practical value of both suspension and undisturbedness because this is the value on which ancient philosophy scholars critical of Pyrrhonism have laid emphasis. The reason for examining the epistemic value of suspension is that doing so will enable a fuller assessment of the significance of Pyrrhonism as a kind of philosophy, which is my primary concern
Conciliationism and the Menace of Scepticism
It is sometimes claimed that conciliatory views on disagreement ultimately lead to either global or widespread scepticism. This is deemed to be a serious problem for conciliationism either because scepticism of either kind is a patently untenable stance or because it poses a serious threat to our intellectual and social lives. In this paper, I first argue that the alleged untenability of both types of scepticism is far from being obvious and should therefore be established rather than taken for granted, and then that those who reject them because of the threat they pose surprisingly confuse pragmatic reasons with epistemic reasons
Suspension, Equipollence, and Inquiry: A Reply to Wieland
It is generally thought that suspension of judgment about a proposition p is the doxastic attitude one is rationally compelled to adopt whenever the epistemic reasons for and against p are equipollent or equally credible, that is, whenever the total body of available evidence bearing on p epistemically justifies neither belief nor disbelief in p. However, in a recent contribution to this journal, Jan Wieland proposes âto broaden the conditions for suspension, and argue that it is rational to suspend belief on a certain issue even if oneâs current evidence is not neutral (or even close to neutral)â. My aim in this paper is to point to a number of problems in Wielandâs position, some of which in connection with the account of Pyrrhonian skepticism found in the extant works of Sextus Empiricus
Again on Sextus on Persuasiveness and Equipollence
This paper engages with Svavar Svavarssonâs recent essay, âSextus Empiricus on Persuasiveness and Equipollence,â arguing against both (i) his interpretation of whether two rival arguments appear equipollent to the Pyrrhonist because he himself is equally persuaded by both of them, and (ii) his interpretation of the way in which the argument from possible disagreement is supposed to induce suspension of judgment in the Pyrrhonist. In so doing, I aim to dispel some serious misunderstandings regarding key aspects of the Pyrrhonistâs skeptical outlook and argumentative practice
Sources of Doxastic Disturbance in Sextus Empiricus
In his account of Pyrrhonism, Sextus Empiricus talks about the disturbance concerning matters of opinion that afflicts his dogmatic rivals and that he himself was afflicted by before his conversion to Pyrrhonism. The aim of the present paper is to identify the distinct sources of doxastic disturbance that can be found in that account, and to determine whether and, if so, how they are related. The thesis to be defended is that it is possible to discern three sources of doxastic disturbance and that two of them are to be explained by reference to the third, which is the real cause of mental distress. The paper also considers whether the thesis in question entails that there is no reason for the Pyrrhonist to suspend judgment across the board, but only to suspend judgment about evaluative matters
Sextus on Ataraxia Revisited
My purpose in this article is to revisit an issue concerning the state of undisturbedness or tranquility (αÌÏαÏαΟÎčÌα) in ancient Pyrrhonism as this skeptical stance is depicted in Sextus
Empiricusâs extant works. The issue in question is whether both the pursuit and the attainment of undisturbedness in matters of opinion should be regarded as defining features of Pyrrhonism not merely from a systematic standpoint that examines Pyrrhonism as a kind of philosophy, but mainly according to Sextusâs own account of that skeptical stance. In exploring this issue, I will develop an interpretation defended in previous work, responding to some objections, discussing alternative interpretations, offering further textual support, and putting forward new arguments. It is my contention that examining whether both the pursuit and the attainment of undisturbedness in matters of opinion are essential to Pyrrhonism will make it possible to gain a more accurate understanding of this brand of skepticism
Pyrrhonian Argumentation: Therapy, Dialectic, and Inquiry
The Pyrrhonist's argumentative practice is characterized by at least four features. First, he makes a therapeutic use of arguments: He employs arguments that differ in their persuasiveness in order to cure his dogmatic patients of the distinct degrees of conceit and rashness that afflict them. Secondly, his arguments are for the most part dialectical: When offering an argument to oppose it to another argument advanced by a given dogmatist, he accepts in propria persona neither the truth of its premises and conclusion nor the validity of its logical form. Thirdly, he avails himself of arguments in his own open-minded inquiry into the truth about a wide range of topics. Fourthly, Pyrrhonian argumentation is oppositional inasmuch as it typically works by producing oppositions among arguments that appear to the Pyrrhonist to be equipollent. In this article, I focus on the first three features with the aim of both shedding some light on them and determining whether they are in tension or coherently relate to each other.Fil: Machuca, Diego Emanuel. Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones CientĂficas y TĂ©cnicas; Argentin
Ancient Skepticism: Overview
Scholarship on ancient skepticism has witnessed a remarkable renaissance in the last three decades. Specialists in ancient philosophy have explored the complex history of the Greco-Roman skeptical traditions and discussed difficult philological and exegetical issues. But they have also assessed the philosophical significance of the various ancient skeptical outlooks. In this first paper, I provide a general presentation of this area of study, while in the two subsequent articles I will focus on some of the topics that have been the object of much attention in the recent literature on ancient skepticism.Fil: Machuca, Diego Emanuel. Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones CientĂficas y TĂ©cnicas; Argentin
El escepticismo Ă©tico de Sexto EmpĂrico
Resumen temporalmente no disponible. La presente obra no cuenta con resumen provisto por el autor.Fil. Machuca, Diego E. Universidad de Buenos Aires. Facultad de FilosofĂa y Letras
- âŠ