67 research outputs found
Unexpectedness and Bayesâ Rule
A great number of methods and of accounts of rationality consider at their foundations some form of Bayesian inference. Yet, Bayesâ rule, because it relies upon probability theory, requires specific axioms to hold (e.g. a measurable space of events). This short document hypothesizes that Bayesâ rule can be seen as a specific instance of a more general inferential template, that can be expressed also in terms of algorithmic complexities, namely through the measure of unexpectedness proposed by Simplicity Theory.</p
Naming Game on Adaptive Weighted Networks
We examine a naming game on an adaptive weighted network. A weight of
connection for a given pair of agents depends on their communication success
rate and determines the probability with which the agents communicate. In some
cases, depending on the parameters of the model, the preference toward
successfully communicating agents is basically negligible and the model behaves
similarly to the naming game on a complete graph. In particular, it quickly
reaches a single-language state, albeit some details of the dynamics are
different from the complete-graph version. In some other cases, the preference
toward successfully communicating agents becomes much more relevant and the
model gets trapped in a multi-language regime. In this case gradual coarsening
and extinction of languages lead to the emergence of a dominant language,
albeit with some other languages still being present. A comparison of
distribution of languages in our model and in the human population is
discussed.Comment: 22 pages, accepted in Artificial Lif
Language structure in the n-object naming game
We examine a naming game with two agents trying to establish a common
vocabulary for n objects. Such efforts lead to the emergence of language that
allows for an efficient communication and exhibits some degree of homonymy and
synonymy. Although homonymy reduces the communication efficiency, it seems to
be a dynamical trap that persists for a long, and perhaps indefinite, time. On
the other hand, synonymy does not reduce the efficiency of communication, but
appears to be only a transient feature of the language. Thus, in our model the
role of synonymy decreases and in the long-time limit it becomes negligible. A
similar rareness of synonymy is observed in present natural languages. The role
of noise, that distorts the communicated words, is also examined. Although, in
general, the noise reduces the communication efficiency, it also regroups the
words so that they are more evenly distributed within the available "verbal"
space.Comment: minor change
The evolution of language: a comparative review
For many years the evolution of language has been seen as a disreputable topic, mired in fanciful "just so stories" about language origins. However, in the last decade a new synthesis of modern linguistics, cognitive neuroscience and neo-Darwinian evolutionary theory has begun to make important contributions to our understanding of the biology and evolution of language. I review some of this recent progress, focusing on the value of the comparative method, which uses data from animal species to draw inferences about language evolution. Discussing speech first, I show how data concerning a wide variety of species, from monkeys to birds, can increase our understanding of the anatomical and neural mechanisms underlying human spoken language, and how bird and whale song provide insights into the ultimate evolutionary function of language. I discuss the ââdescended larynxâ â of humans, a peculiar adaptation for speech that has received much attention in the past, which despite earlier claims is not uniquely human. Then I will turn to the neural mechanisms underlying spoken language, pointing out the difficulties animals apparently experience in perceiving hierarchical structure in sounds, and stressing the importance of vocal imitation in the evolution of a spoken language. Turning to ultimate function, I suggest that communication among kin (especially between parents and offspring) played a crucial but neglected role in driving language evolution. Finally, I briefly discuss phylogeny, discussing hypotheses that offer plausible routes to human language from a non-linguistic chimp-like ancestor. I conclude that comparative data from living animals will be key to developing a richer, more interdisciplinary understanding of our most distinctively human trait: language
Cultural transmission and biological markets
Active cultural transmission of fitness-enhancing behavior (sometimes called âteachingâ) can be seen as a costly strategy: one for which its evolutionary stability poses a Darwinian puzzle. In this article, we offer a biological market model of cultural transmission that substitutes or complements existing kin selection-based proposals for the evolution of cultural capacities. We explicitly demonstrate how a biological market can account for the evolution of teaching when individual learners are the exclusive focus of social learning (such as in a fast-changing environment). We also show how this biological market can affect the dynamics of cumulative culture. The model works best when it is difficult to have access to the observation of the behavior without the help of the actor. However, in contrast to previous non-mathematical hypotheses for the evolution of teaching, we show how teaching evolves even when innovations are insufficiently opaque and therefore vulnerable to acquisition by emulators via inadvertent transmission. Furthermore, teaching in a biological market is an important precondition for enhancing individual learning abilitie
L'imaginaire de la narration : une approche cognitive
National audienceImaginer une histoire est lâune des capacitĂ©s les plus apprĂ©ciĂ©es dans nos sociĂ©tĂ©s, si lâon en juge par le statut social rĂ©servĂ© aux meilleurs conteurs dont certains, les acadĂ©miciens, se voient confĂ©rer le statut « dâimmortel ». Pour inventer une bonne histoire, il ne suffit pas de mettre des Ă©vĂ©nements imaginaires bout Ă bout. Il ne suffit pas non plus que ces Ă©vĂ©nements sâenchaĂźnent de maniĂšre cohĂ©rente : le rĂ©cit de ma journĂ©e dâhier ne possĂšde aucune valeur narrative, bien que tous les Ă©lĂ©ments qui la composent puissent ĂȘtre logiquement justifiĂ©s. Quelles sont les propriĂ©tĂ©s dont doit jouir une histoire pour ĂȘtre une histoire ? Il est possible de rĂ©pondre Ă cette question en se plaçant dans le cadre de la modĂ©lisation cognitive. La notion centrale qui sera dĂ©veloppĂ©e ici est celle de « simplicitĂ© cachĂ©e ». Pour ĂȘtre intĂ©ressante, une situation imaginaire doit comporter une « rĂ©vĂ©lation » qui simplifie une situation perçue comme complexe. Le cadre conceptuel qui sera dĂ©veloppĂ© peut avoir des retombĂ©es qui dĂ©bordent le domaine de la production narrative. Il concerne potentiellement toute crĂ©ation de lâesprit censĂ©e « intĂ©resser » autrui. Ceci inclut les rĂ©cits, mais aussi les objets ou les projets, dĂšs lors que ces objets ou ces projets se voient dotĂ©s dâune valeur narrative.</p
- âŠ