639 research outputs found
The Importance of Bruno Latour for Philosophy
This article explores the importance of French thinker, Bruno Latour, for academic philosophy and addresses the question of why, when he has an enthusiastic following in a range of disciplines including sociology, anthropology and the fine arts, he has been largely overlooked by academic philosophers
Skirmishes
"One of the fifty most influential living philosophers, a âself-promoting charlatanâ (Brian Leiter), and the orchestrator of an âonline orgy of stupidityâ (Ray Brassier). In Skirmishes: With Friends, Enemies, and Neutrals, Graham Harman responds with flair and wit to some of his best-known critics and fellow travelers. Pulling no punches, Harman gives a masterclass in philosophical argumentation by dissecting, analyzing, and countering their criticism, be it from the Husserlian, Heideggerian, or Derridean corner. At the same time, Skirmishes provides an excellent introduction to the hottest debates in Speculative Realism and Object-Oriented Ontology, a speculative style of philosophy long foreclosed by the biases of mainstream continental thought, but which has turned in recent years into one of the most encompassing philosophies of our time, with a major impact on the arts, humanities, and architecture.
Part One considers four prominent books on speculative realism. In dialogue with Tom Sparrowâs The End of Phenomenology, Harman expresses agreement with Sparrowâs critique while taking issue with Lee Braverâs âtransgressive realismâ as not realist enough. Turning to Steven Shaviroâs The Universe of Things, Harman defends his own object-oriented model against Shaviroâs brand of process philosophy, while also engaging in side-debate with Levi R. Bryantâs distinction between virtual proper being and local manifestations. In the third chapter, on Peter Grattonâs Speculative Realism: Problems and Prospects, Harman opposes the authorâs attempt to use Derridean notions of time and difference against Speculative Realism, in what amounts to his most extensive engagement with Derrida to date. Chapter Four gives us Harmanâs response to Peter Wolfendaleâs massive polemic in Object-Oriented Philosophy, which he shows is based on a failed criticism of Harmanâs reading of Heidegger and a grumpy commitment to rationalist kitsch.
Part Two responds to a series of briefer criticisms of object-oriented ontology. When Alberto Toscano accuses Harman and Bruno Latour of âneo-monadologicalâ and anti-scientific thinking, Harman responds that the philosophical factors pushing Leibniz into monadology are still valid today. When Christopher Norris mocks Harman for seeing merit in the occasionalist school, he shows why Norrisâs middle-of-the-road scientific realism misses the point. In response to Dan Zahaviâs contention that phenomenology has little to learn from speculative realism, Harman exposes the holes in Zahaviâs reasoning. In a final response, Harman gives a point-by-point answer to Stephen Mulhallâs critical foray in the London Review of Books. Amidst these lively debates, Harman sheds new light on what he regards as the central bias of philosophical modernism, which he terms the taxonomical standpoint. It is a book sure to provoke lively controversy among both friends and foes of object-oriented thought.
The Problem With Metzinger
This article provides a critical treatment of the ontology underlying Thomas Metzinger's Being No One. Metzinger asserts that interdisciplinary empirical work must replace âarmchair' a priori intuitions into the nature of reality; nonetheless, his own position is riddled with unquestioned a priori assumptions. His central claim that âno one has or has ever had a self' is meant to have an ominous and futuristic ring, but merely repeats a familiar philosophical approach to individuals, which are undermined by reducing them downward to their material underpinnings, and âovermined' by reducing them upward to their functional effects. Ultimately, Metzinger blends a rigid form of traditional materialism with an ontology of processes and events that is too reminiscent of late 1990's continental philosophy. In both directions, the novelty and fertility of Metzinger's position can be called into question
On the Supposed Societies of Chemicals, Atoms and Stars in Gabriel Tarde
It is commonly believed that the French sociologist Gabriel Tarde allows even for inanimate objects such as chemicals, atoms, and stars to be topics of sociology. This article claims otherwise. Tarde is an arch-reductionist for whom nothing exists below the tiniest micro-level of the cosmos. His theory of monads is by no means an adequate sociology of medium- or large-sized things.https://fount.aucegypt.edu/faculty_book_chapters/1763/thumbnail.jp
Time, Space, Essence, and Eidos: A New Theory of Causation
This article attempts to develop the abandoned occasionalist model of causation into a credible present-day theory. If objects can never exhaust one another through their relations, it is hard to know how they can ever interact at all. This article handles the problem by dividing objects into two kinds: the real objects that emerge from Heidegger's tool-analysis and the intentional objects of Husserl's phenomenology. Each of these objects turns out to be split by an additional rift between the object as an enduring unit and its plurality of traits. This explains Heidegger's notorious âfourfold' model of the thing. This article shows that Heidegger's Geviert must be reinterpreted as a system of four tensions that can be identified as time, space, essence, and eidos. Time and space can no longer be left as peerless dimensions of the cosmos. Instead, they are shown to arise from the tensions between things and their qualities. And for this reason they are joined by essence (in the classical sense of the term) and eidos (in Husserl's sense, not Plato's) as two out of four basic features of the fabric of the world
Concerning Stephen Hawkingâs Claim that Philosophy is Dead
The article begins from Stephen Hawking's well-known claim that philosophy is dead, and considers several other quotations in which philosophy is either belittled or subordinated outright to the natural sciences. This subordination requires a downward reductionism that is paralleled by the upward reductionism of the linguistic turn and social constructionist theories. Rather than undermining or overmining mid-sized individual entities, philosophy must deal with objects on their own terms. This suggests a possible tactical alliance between philosophy and the arts
Skirmishes
"One of the fifty most influential living philosophers, a âself-promoting charlatanâ (Brian Leiter), and the orchestrator of an âonline orgy of stupidityâ (Ray Brassier). In Skirmishes: With Friends, Enemies, and Neutrals, Graham Harman responds with flair and wit to some of his best-known critics and fellow travelers. Pulling no punches, Harman gives a masterclass in philosophical argumentation by dissecting, analyzing, and countering their criticism, be it from the Husserlian, Heideggerian, or Derridean corner. At the same time, Skirmishes provides an excellent introduction to the hottest debates in Speculative Realism and Object-Oriented Ontology, a speculative style of philosophy long foreclosed by the biases of mainstream continental thought, but which has turned in recent years into one of the most encompassing philosophies of our time, with a major impact on the arts, humanities, and architecture.
Part One considers four prominent books on speculative realism. In dialogue with Tom Sparrowâs The End of Phenomenology, Harman expresses agreement with Sparrowâs critique while taking issue with Lee Braverâs âtransgressive realismâ as not realist enough. Turning to Steven Shaviroâs The Universe of Things, Harman defends his own object-oriented model against Shaviroâs brand of process philosophy, while also engaging in side-debate with Levi R. Bryantâs distinction between virtual proper being and local manifestations. In the third chapter, on Peter Grattonâs Speculative Realism: Problems and Prospects, Harman opposes the authorâs attempt to use Derridean notions of time and difference against Speculative Realism, in what amounts to his most extensive engagement with Derrida to date. Chapter Four gives us Harmanâs response to Peter Wolfendaleâs massive polemic in Object-Oriented Philosophy, which he shows is based on a failed criticism of Harmanâs reading of Heidegger and a grumpy commitment to rationalist kitsch.
Part Two responds to a series of briefer criticisms of object-oriented ontology. When Alberto Toscano accuses Harman and Bruno Latour of âneo-monadologicalâ and anti-scientific thinking, Harman responds that the philosophical factors pushing Leibniz into monadology are still valid today. When Christopher Norris mocks Harman for seeing merit in the occasionalist school, he shows why Norrisâs middle-of-the-road scientific realism misses the point. In response to Dan Zahaviâs contention that phenomenology has little to learn from speculative realism, Harman exposes the holes in Zahaviâs reasoning. In a final response, Harman gives a point-by-point answer to Stephen Mulhallâs critical foray in the London Review of Books. Amidst these lively debates, Harman sheds new light on what he regards as the central bias of philosophical modernism, which he terms the taxonomical standpoint. It is a book sure to provoke lively controversy among both friends and foes of object-oriented thought.
Matter and Society. Response to Orensanz
This article is a response to Martin Orensanzâs argument that object-oriented ontology ought to accept the existence of matter as both a sensual and a real object. That matter can exist as a sensual object is a point immediately granted, since âsensual objectâ is such a broad term that nothing could be excluded from this designation. Yet I argue that this is not the case with respect to real objects, which must exist independently of any other entity that might encounter them. This leads to a related debate on whether parthood is transitive, in which Orensanz takes up a recent argument of Daniel Korman while I defend the modified Aristotelian position that only the proximate parts of an object can be said to belong to it in the strict sense
L'unica via d'uscita dalla filosofia moderna
This article contends that the central principle of modern philosophy is obscured by a side-debate between two opposed camps that are united in accepting a deeper flawed premise. Consider the powerful critiques of Kantian philosophy offered by Quentin Meillassoux and Bruno Latour, respectively. These two thinkers criticize Kant for opposite reasons: Meillassoux because Kant collapses thought and world into a permanent âcorrelateâ without isolated terms, and Latour because Kant tries to purify thought and world from each other rather than realizing that they are always combined in âhybridâ form. What both critiques tacitly accept is the notion that âthoughtâ and âworldâ are the two major poles of the universe. I claim that this stems from the post-Cartesian assumption that thought and world are the two basic kinds of things that exist. The name âonto-taxonomyâ is introduced for this view
- âŠ