18 research outputs found

    Extrinsic democratic proceduralism: a modest defence

    No full text
    Disagreement among philosophers over the proper justification for political institutions is far from a new phenomenon. Thus, it should not come as a surprise that there is substantial room for dissent on this matter within democratic theory. As is well known, instrumentalism and proceduralism represent the two primary viewpoints that democrats can adopt to vindicate democratic legitimacy. While the former notoriously derives the value of democracy from its outcomes, the latter claims that a democratic decision-making process is inherently valuable. This article has two aims. First, it introduces three variables with which we can thoroughly categorise the aforementioned approaches. Second, it argues that the more promising version of proceduralism is extrinsic, rather than intrinsic, and that extrinsically procedural accounts can appeal to other values in the justification of democracy without translating into instrumentalism. This article is organised as follows. I present what I consider to be the ‘implicit view’ in the justification of democracy. Then, I analyse each of the three variables in a different section. Finally, I raise an objection against procedural views grounded in relational equality, which cannot account for the idea that democracy is a necessary condition for political legitimacy

    Right or Wrong, It’s Democracy. Legitimacy, Justification and the Independent Criterion

    Get PDF
    Contemporary normative theories of democracy generally aim to show that democratic outcomes are legitimate and hence they ought to be obeyed. As it is known, the battlefield is split between two major approaches: instrumentalism and proceduralism. Yet, many philosophers of both approaches seem to overlook one distinction that ought to be crucial in their reasoning - or so I argue in this paper. First, I highlight this distinction between the justification of outcomes on one hand, and their legitimacy on the other. If the justification of outcomes is unachievable given circumstances of pluralism and disagreement, their legitimacy derives from the procedures that bring them about. Hence both accounts present a justification of democratic procedures by reference to a criterion that is independent from the procedures themselves. Second, I propose to distinguish between instrumentalism and proceduralism on the basis of the connection that these approaches draw between the justifying criterion and democratic procedures. While for instrumentalism this is contingent and indirect, for proceduralism it is direct and necessary. Finally, I take into account two well-known taxonomies in epistemic democracy, which are provided by David Estlund and Fabienne Peter, and I argue that both blur the distinction between the justification of outcomes and their legitimacy and are thus unsatisfactory and misleading

    From right to might, and back: Functional legitimacy as a realist value

    No full text
    For political realists, legitimacy is a central requirement for the desirability of political institutions. Their detractors contend that it is either descriptive, and thus devoid of critical potential, or it relies on some moralist value that realists reject. We defend a functionalist reading of realist legitimacy: descriptive legitimacy, that is, the capacity of a political institution to generate beliefs in its right to rule as opposed to commanding through coercion alone, is desirable in virtue of its functional role. First, descriptive legitimacy plays an evaluative role: Institutions can fail to convince citizens that they have a right to rule and can be ranked by how well they do so. Second, descriptive legitimacy plays a normative role, because if an institution fails to convince subjects of its right to rule, this gives them a reason not to comply with its directives, even if it satisfies philosophers' standards for possessing such right

    De la démocratie en temps de Covid-19

    No full text
    Demandez Ă  un Ă©tudiant de premiĂšre annĂ©e ce qu’est la dĂ©mocratie, et il vous rĂ©pondra trĂšs certainement qu’il s’agit d’un rĂ©gime politique dans lequel le peuple Ă©lit ses dirigeants. [premier paragraphe

    Quand le Covid-19 met en lumiÚre la crise de responsabilité politique

    No full text
    contribution Ă  un site webAu premier tour des Ă©lections municipales le 15 mars dernier, le taux d’abstention a atteint un niveau historique, mais peu surprenant au regard de la crise sanitaire, de 55,3 %. Au second tour, le 28 juin, seuls 41,6 % de ceux appelĂ©s Ă  voter se sont dĂ©placĂ©s aux urnes. [Premier paragraphe

    The Sources of Political Normativity: the Case for Instrumental and Epistemic Normativity in Political Realism

    No full text
    This article argues that political realists have at least two strategies to provide distinctively political normative judgments that have nothing to do with morality. The first ground is instrumental normativity, which states that if we believe that something is a necessary means to a goal we have, we have a reason to do it. In politics, certain means are required by any ends we may intend to purse. The second ground is epistemic normativity, stating that if something is (empirically) true, this gives us a reason to believe it. In politics, there are certain empirical regularities that ought to be acknowledged for what they are. Both sources are flawed. Instrumental normativity only requires coherence between attitudes and beliefs, and one can hang on to false beliefs to preserve attitudes incompatible with reality. I may desire to eschew power relations, and as such imagine politics to be like a camping trip. Epistemic normativity, on the other hand, operates critically, striking down existing normative claims. It shows us that politics is nothing like a camping trip, but it doesn't tell us what we should do about it (beyond abandoning some false beliefs). We conclude by showing that if the two are taken together, they remedy each other flaws

    Egalité démocratique et tirage au sort

    No full text
    La thĂ©orie dĂ©mocratique contemporaine entretient une relation ambivalente avec les Ă©lections. Alors que les points de vue agrĂ©gatifs et minimalistes les considĂšrent comme une institution centrale de la dĂ©mocratie reprĂ©sentative , les conceptions plus riches de la dĂ©mocratie n’ont pas nĂ©cessairement de penchant pour elles. Les thĂ©ories dĂ©libĂ©ratives ont tendance Ă  nĂ©gliger les Ă©lections pour se concentrer sur la dĂ©libĂ©ration publique, c’est-Ă -dire sur le processus continu de formation de l’opinion et d’échange de raisons qui se produit entre les Ă©lections . Les thĂ©ories participatives ont Ă©galement tendance Ă  les Ă©carter en faveur d’une vision moins agonistique et plus coopĂ©rative de l’action politique . Par consĂ©quent, peu d’attention normative a Ă©tĂ© accordĂ©e dans la littĂ©rature rĂ©cente Ă  ce moment trĂšs distinctif de la vie dĂ©mocratique, Ă  quelques notables exceptions prĂšs . Une consĂ©quence naturelle est que la plupart des thĂ©oriciens font appel Ă  des expĂ©riences dĂ©libĂ©ratives telles que les jurys de citoyens et les mini-publics comme rĂ©ponse efficace aux prĂ©occupations dĂ©mocratiques actuelles . Le tirage au sort peut ainsi ĂȘtre prĂ©sentĂ© comme une alternative prĂ©fĂ©rable Ă  l’élection, car il garantit une reprĂ©sentation descriptive, Ă©vite la capture de l’État par des Ă©lites puissantes et promet des rĂ©sultats substantiellement meilleurs. Alors que de nombreux thĂ©oriciens s’intĂ©ressent aux moyens de complĂ©ter les institutions Ă©lectorales par des organes dĂ©libĂ©ratifs non Ă©lectoraux , certains chercheurs se dĂ©barrasseraient volontiers des Ă©lections . Le moment est-il venu de les abandonner ? Cet article se concentre sur une affirmation spĂ©cifique que beaucoup de partisans du tirage au sort ont avancĂ©e, Ă  savoir que celui-ci serait plus Ă©galitaire que les Ă©lections, et vise Ă  la rejeter. D’autres chercheurs ont dĂ©jĂ  critiquĂ© le tirage au sort pour diverses raisons. Landa et Pevnick , ainsi qu’Umbers objectent qu’il ne permet pas d’obtenir les amĂ©liorations instrumentales du gouvernement promises par ses promoteurs ; Ceva et Ottonelli , ainsi que Lafont nient que les critiques lotocratiques des Ă©lections reflĂštent une comprĂ©hension adĂ©quate de l’autoritĂ© dĂ©mocratique en tant que forme d’autonomie collective ; et Umbers soutient Ă©galement que la lotocratie est en contradiction avec les principes de justice distributive et d’égalitĂ© sociale . En complĂ©ment Ă  ces critiques rĂ©centes, nous soutenons que la vision de l’égalitĂ© politique qui sous-tend le tirage au sort est problĂ©matique et peu convaincante
    corecore