363 research outputs found

    Spacetime topology from the tomographic histories approach: Part II

    Full text link
    As an inverse problem, we recover the topology of the effective spacetime that a system lies in, in an operational way. This means that from a series of experiments we get a set of points corresponding to events. This continues the previous work done by the authors. Here we use the existence of upper bound in the speed of transfer of matter and information to induce a partial order on the set of events. While the actual partial order is not known in our operational set up, the grouping of events to (unordered) subsets corresponding to possible histories, is given. From this we recover the partial order up to certain ambiguities that are then classified. Finally two different ways to recover the topology are sketched and their interpretation is discussed.Comment: 21 pages, slight change in title and certain minor corrections in this second version. To apear in IJT

    Spacetime topology from the tomographic histories approach I: Non-relativistic Case

    Full text link
    The tomographic histories approach is presented. As an inverse problem, we recover in an operational way the effective topology of the extended configuration space of a system. This means that from a series of experiments we get a set of points corresponding to events. The difference between effective and actual topology is drawn. We deduce the topology of the extended configuration space of a non-relativistic system, using certain concepts from the consistent histories approach to Quantum Mechanics, such as the notion of a record. A few remarks about the case of a relativistic system, preparing the ground for a forthcoming paper sequel to this, are made in the end.Comment: 19 pages, slight chang in title and corrected typos in second version. To appear to a special proceedings issue (Glafka 2004) of the International Journal of Theoretical Physic

    Conservation Laws in the Quantum Mechanics of Closed Systems

    Get PDF
    We investigate conservation laws in the quantum mechanics of closed systems. We review an argument showing that exact decoherence implies the exact conservation of quantities that commute with the Hamiltonian including the total energy and total electric charge. However, we also show that decoherence severely limits the alternatives which can be included in sets of histories which assess the conservation of these quantities when they are not coupled to a long-range field arising from a fundamental symmetry principle. We then examine the realistic cases of electric charge coupled to the electromagnetic field and mass coupled to spacetime curvature and show that when alternative values of charge and mass decohere, they always decohere exactly and are exactly conserved as a consequence of their couplings to long-range fields. Further, while decohering histories that describe fluctuations in total charge and mass are also subject to the limitations mentioned above, we show that these do not, in fact, restrict {\it physical} alternatives and are therefore not really limitations at all.Comment: 22 pages, report UCSBTH-94-4, LA-UR-94-2101, CGPG-94/10-

    Diffeomorphisms as Symplectomorphisms in History Phase Space: Bosonic String Model

    Get PDF
    The structure of the history phase space G\cal G of a covariant field system and its history group (in the sense of Isham and Linden) is analyzed on an example of a bosonic string. The history space G\cal G includes the time map T\sf T from the spacetime manifold (the two-sheet) Y\cal Y to a one-dimensional time manifold T\cal T as one of its configuration variables. A canonical history action is posited on G\cal G such that its restriction to the configuration history space yields the familiar Polyakov action. The standard Dirac-ADM action is shown to be identical with the canonical history action, the only difference being that the underlying action is expressed in two different coordinate charts on G\cal G. The canonical history action encompasses all individual Dirac-ADM actions corresponding to different choices T\sf T of foliating Y\cal Y. The history Poisson brackets of spacetime fields on G\cal G induce the ordinary Poisson brackets of spatial fields in the instantaneous phase space G0{\cal G}_{0} of the Dirac-ADM formalism. The canonical history action is manifestly invariant both under spacetime diffeomorphisms DiffY\cal Y and temporal diffeomorphisms DiffT\cal T. Both of these diffeomorphisms are explicitly represented by symplectomorphisms on the history phase space G\cal G. The resulting classical history phase space formalism is offered as a starting point for projection operator quantization and consistent histories interpretation of the bosonic string model.Comment: 45 pages, no figure

    Decoherence and classical predictability of phase space histories

    Get PDF
    We consider the decoherence of phase space histories in a class of quantum Brownian motion models, consisting of a particle moving in a potential V(x)V(x) in interaction with a heat bath at temperature TT and dissipation gamma, in the Markovian regime. The evolution of the density operator for this open system is thus described by a non-unitary master equation. The phase space histories of the system are described by a class of quasiprojectors. Generalizing earlier results of Hagedorn and Omn\`es, we show that a phase space projector onto a phase space cell Γ\Gamma is approximately evolved under the master equation into another phase space projector onto the classical dissipative evolution of Γ\Gamma, and with a certain amount of degradation due to the noise produced by the environment. We thus show that histories of phase space samplings approximately decohere, and that the probabilities for these histories are peaked about classical dissipative evolution, with a width of peaking depending on the size of the noise.Comment: 34 pages, LATEX, revised version to avoid LATEX error

    Decoherence of Histories and Hydrodynamic Equations for a Linear Oscillator Chain

    Full text link
    We investigate the decoherence of histories of local densities for linear oscillators models. It is shown that histories of local number, momentum and energy density are approximately decoherent, when coarse-grained over sufficiently large volumes. Decoherence arises directly from the proximity of these variables to exactly conserved quantities (which are exactly decoherent), and not from environmentally-induced decoherence. We discuss the approach to local equilibrium and the subsequent emergence of hydrodynamic equations for the local densities.Comment: 37 pages, RevTe

    Types of quantum information

    Full text link
    Quantum, in contrast to classical, information theory, allows for different incompatible types (or species) of information which cannot be combined with each other. Distinguishing these incompatible types is useful in understanding the role of the two classical bits in teleportation (or one bit in one-bit teleportation), for discussing decoherence in information-theoretic terms, and for giving a proper definition, in quantum terms, of ``classical information.'' Various examples (some updating earlier work) are given of theorems which relate different incompatible kinds of information, and thus have no counterparts in classical information theory.Comment: Minor changes so as to agree with published versio

    Decoherence of Hydrodynamic Histories: A Simple Spin Model

    Get PDF
    In the context of the decoherent histories approach to the quantum mechanics of closed systems, Gell-Mann and Hartle have argued that the variables typically characterizing the quasiclassical domain of a large complex system are the integrals over small volumes of locally conserved densities -- hydrodynamic variables. The aim of this paper is to exhibit some simple models in which approximate decoherence arises as a result of local conservation. We derive a formula which shows the explicit connection between local conservation and approximate decoherence. We then consider a class of models consisting of a large number of weakly interacting components, in which the projections onto local densities may be decomposed into projections onto one of two alternatives of the individual components. The main example we consider is a one-dimensional chain of locally coupled spins, and the projections are onto the total spin in a subsection of the chain. We compute the decoherence functional for histories of local densities, in the limit when the number of components is very large. We find that decoherence requires two things: the smearing volumes must be sufficiently large to ensure approximate conservation, and the local densities must be partitioned into sufficiently large ranges to ensure protection against quantum fluctuations.Comment: Standard TeX, 36 pages + 3 figures (postscript) Revised abstract and introduction. To appear in Physical Review

    Decoherence Functional and Probability Interpretation

    Get PDF
    We confirm that the diagonal elements of the Gell-Mann and Hartle's decoherence decoherence functional are equal to the relative frequencies of the results of many identical experiments, when a set of alternative histories decoheres. We consider both cases of the pure and mixed initial states.Comment: 9 pages, UCSBTH-92-40 and MMC-M-

    Topos Theory and Consistent Histories: The Internal Logic of the Set of all Consistent Sets

    Get PDF
    A major problem in the consistent-histories approach to quantum theory is contending with the potentially large number of consistent sets of history propositions. One possibility is to find a scheme in which a unique set is selected in some way. However, in this paper we consider the alternative approach in which all consistent sets are kept, leading to a type of `many world-views' picture of the quantum theory. It is shown that a natural way of handling this situation is to employ the theory of varying sets (presheafs) on the space \B of all Boolean subalgebras of the orthoalgebra \UP of history propositions. This approach automatically includes the feature whereby probabilistic predictions are meaningful only in the context of a consistent set of history propositions. More strikingly, it leads to a picture in which the `truth values', or `semantic values' of such contextual predictions are not just two-valued (\ie true and false) but instead lie in a larger logical algebra---a Heyting algebra---whose structure is determined by the space \B of Boolean subalgebras of \UP.Comment: 28 pages, LaTe
    • …
    corecore