10,798 research outputs found
The modal account of luck revisited
According to the canonical formulation of the modal account of luck [e.g. Pritchard (2005)], an event is lucky just when that event occurs in the actual world but not in a wide class of the nearest possible worlds where the relevant conditions for that event are the same as in the actual world. This paper argues, with reference to a novel variety of counterexample, that it is a mistake to focus, when assessing a given event for luckiness, on events distributed over just the nearest possible worlds. More specifically, our objection to the canonical formulation of the modal account of luck reveals that whether an event is lucky depends crucially on events distributed over all possible worldsâviz., across the modal universe. It is shown that an amended modal account of luck which respects this point has the additional virtue of avoiding a notable kind of counterexample to modal accounts of luck proposed by Lackey (2008)
INTERNATIONAL TRADE: HOW IT AFFECTS VIRGINIA AGRICULTURE
International Relations/Trade,
Not knowing a cat is a cat: analyticity and knowledge ascriptions
It is a natural assumption in mainstream epistemological theory that ascriptions of knowledge of a proposition p track strength of epistemic position vis-Ă -vis p. It is equally natural to assume that the strength of oneâs epistemic position is maximally high in cases where p concerns a simple analytic truth (as opposed to an empirical truth). For instance, it seems reasonable to suppose that one's epistemic position vis-Ă -vis âa cat is a catâ is harder to improve than one's position vis-Ă -vis âa cat is on the matâ, and consequently, that the former is at least as unambiguous a case of knowledge as the latter. The current paper, however, presents empirical evidence which challenges this intuitive line of reasoning. Our study on the epistemic intuitions of hundreds of academic philosophers supports the idea that simple and uncontroversial analytic propositions are less likely to qualify as knowledge than empirical ones. We show that our results, though at odds with orthodox theories of knowledge in mainstream epistemology, can be explained in a way consistent with Wittgenstein's remarks on 'hinge propositions' or with Stalnaker's pragmatics of assertion. We then present and evaluate a number of lines of response mainstream theories of knowledge could appeal to in accommodating our results. Finally, we show how each line of response runs into some prima facie difficulties. Thus, our observed asymmetry between knowing âa cat is a catâ and knowing âa cat is on the matâ presents a puzzle which mainstream epistemology needs to resolve
Airline Crew Scheduling with Potts Neurons
A Potts feedback neural network approach for finding good solutions to
resource allocation problems with a non-fixed topology is presented. As a
target application the airline crew scheduling problem is chosen. The
topological complication is handled by means of a propagator defined in terms
of Potts neurons. The approach is tested on artificial random problems tuned to
resemble real-world conditions. Very good results are obtained for a variety of
problem sizes. The computer time demand for the approach only grows like
\mbox{(number of flights)}^3. A realistic problem typically is solved within
minutes, partly due to a prior reduction of the problem size, based on an
analysis of the local arrival/departure structure at the single airportsComment: 9 pages LaTeX, 3 postscript figures, uufiles forma
Embodied Transitions in Michel de Montaigne
Sixteenth-century French philosopher Michel de Montaigne was one of the first writers to reflect on embodiment. âI am myself the matter of my book,â he proclaims in the introduction to his Essays. Montaigne writes about various moments of embodied transitions: a near-death experience, reflections on aging and cognitive decline, and a lengthy discussion of how to cope in the face of devastating loss. Taking an interdisciplinary perspective by analyzing the relationship between embodiment, health representations, and geropsychological themes, this chapter analyzes Montaigneâs in-between moments, arguing that Montaigneâs essaysâinnovative in their own timeâremain important in discussing embodied transitions today
Sins, Sex, and Secrets: The Legacy of Confession from the Decameron to the Heptaméron
A quick digital search for the term âconfessionâ in Boccaccioâs Decameron yields 75 results (Decameron Web). Confession in Boccacioâs text is conspicuously present and, I argue, not coincidental: it highlights the increased attention to the sacrament after the Fourth Lateran Council made annual confession mandatory in 1215. Decameron 1.1 depicts a false confession performed by a wicked man on his deathbed. His confessor follows the protocol of confession manuals, which began to appear in increasing number following 1215, but his interpretive skills do not extend beyond the questions he is bound by protocol to ask. In Boccaccioâs world, confession, though important, is rather formulaic and prone to manipulation by wicked evil-doers such as the man in 1.1.
A few centuries later, wicked evil-doers continue to manipulate confessional narrative in Marguerite de Navarreâs HeptamĂ©ron (1559). Hers is a text that proclaims to model itself after the Decameronâ with a few significant alterations. The Prologue establishes that all stories be true. Storytelling takes place on the grounds of an abbey, an explicitly confessional space. References to confession in Margueriteâs text highlight the shifting status of confession in the sixteenth century. This paper explores the ways in which Marguerite de Navarre takes Boccacioâs sacramental legacy and transforms it into a confessional space where some of the most pressing concerns of her time come to light
Detection of Neonatal Calf Diarrhea Virus (NCDV) and Human Infant Reolike Diarrhea Virus
The purpose of this study was to develop a diagnostic test and conduct a survey for the neonatal calf diarrhea virus (NCDV) and human infant reolike diarrhea virus. Two immunologic methods were developed in this investigation.
Immune electron microscopy (IEM) and the fluorescent viral precipitin test (FVPT) are the methods used to detect NCDV and the human virus. Both methods are based upon the principle that viral aggregates form when the virus is reacted with anti-NCDV antibody. Aggregates in the IEM method are negatively stained and observed with the use of an electron microscope. Fluorescein labeled antibody is used in the FVPT and the resultant aggregates are observed with the use of epifluorescence microscopy.
IEM and the FVPT are sensitive, specific and rapid. The sample is examined within two hours after arriving at the laboratory. Both methods are useful; however, the FVPT allows for more general application because it requires less technical skill and relatively inexpensive equipment is used.
NCDV was found in 41% (14/34) of diarrheic calves tested in northern Utah and NCDV antibody was in 100% (16/16) of adult animals tested. The human reolike virus was found in 80% (4/5) of the infants tested
What Women Know: The Power of \u3ci\u3eSavoir\u3c/i\u3e in Marguerite de Navarreâs \u3ci\u3eHeptamĂ©ron\u3c/i\u3e
The verbs savoir and connaĂźtre appear in central moments in the HeptamĂ©ron. Knowledgeâas it appears in the frame narrative and in the novellasâcan be a way for men and women to debate, among many other things, the relationship between the sexes. When women use this word, or when they demonstrate that they know something, it creates the space to participate â not always unambiguously â in otherwise male-dominated conversations. How Marguerite writes about the acquisition, possession, fragmentation, or loss of knowledge, underscores her interest in exploring the role of women in communities of knowledge
- âŠ