135 research outputs found
Kant on the Logical Form of Singular Judgments
At A71/B96â7 Kant explains that singular judgements are âspecialâ because
they stand to the general ones as Einheit to Unendlichkeit. The reference to
Einheit brings to mind the category of unity and hence raises a spectre of
circularity in Kantâs explanation. I aim to remove this spectre by interpreting
the Einheit-Unendlichkeit contrast in light of the logical distinctions
among universal, particular and singular judgments shared by Kant and
his logician predecessors. This interpretation has a further implication for
resolving a controversy over the correlation between the logical moments
of quantity (universal, particular, singular) and the categorial ones (unity,
plurality, totality)
From Logical Calculus to Logical FormalityâWhat Kant Did with Eulerâs Circles
John Venn has the âuneasy suspicionâ that the stagnation in mathematical logic between J. H. Lambert and George Boole was due to Kantâs âdisastrous effect on logical method,â namely the âstrictest preservation [of logic] from mathematical encroachment.â Kantâs actual position is more nuanced, however. In this chapter, I tease out the nuances by examining his use of Leonhard Eulerâs circles and comparing it with Eulerâs own use. I do so in light of the developments in logical calculus from G. W. Leibniz to Lambert and Gottfried Ploucquet. While Kant is evidently open to using mathematical tools in logic, his main concern is to clarify what mathematical tools can be used to achieve. For without such clarification, all efforts at introducing mathematical tools into logic would be blind if not complete waste of time. In the end, Kant would stress, the means provided by formal logic at best help us to express and order what we already know in some sense. No matter how much mathematical notations may enhance the precision of this function of formal logic, it does not change the fact that no truths can, strictly speaking, be revealed or established by means of those notations
Epigenesis of Pure Reason and the Source of Pure Cognitions
Kant describes logic as âthe science that exhaustively presents and strictly proves nothing but the formal rules of all thinkingâ. (Bviii-ix) But what is the source of our cognition of such rules (âlogical cognitionâ for short)? He makes no concerted effort to address this question. It will nonetheless become clear that the question is a philosophically significant one for him, to which he can see three possible answers: those representations are innate, derived from experience, or originally acquired a priori. Although he gives no explicit argument for the third answer, he seems committed to itâespecially given his views on the source of pure concepts of the understanding and on the nature of logic.
It takes careful preparatory work to gather all the essential materials for motivating and reconstructing Kantâs âoriginal acquisitionâ account of logical cognition. I shall proceed in two sections.
In section 1, I analyze Kantâs argument that pure concepts of the understanding (or intellectual concepts)âas one kind of pure cognitionâmust be acquired originally and a priori. My analysis partly concerns his varied attitudes toward Crusiusâs and Leibnizâs versions of the nativist account of such concepts. I give special attention to how Kant characterizes the nativist account and his own âoriginal acquisitionâ account in terms of âpreformationâ and âepigenesisâ. My goal is, firstly, to tease out the sense in which Kant grants that there must be an innate ground (or preformation) for the derivation of pure concepts and, secondly, to introduceâand pave the way for answeringâthe question about the source of logical cognition.
In section 2, in light of Kantâs reference to Locke and Leibniz as the greatest reformers of philosophy (including logic) in their times (Log, AA 9: 32), I examine the Lockean and Leibnizian approaches to logic, respectively. Both approaches are âphysiologicalâ by Kantâs standard and are directly opposed to his own strictly critical method. I explain how this methodological move shapes Kantâs view that representations of logical rules must be originally acquired a priori. This acquisition involves a kind of radical epigenesis of pure reason: unlike the acquisition of pure concepts, it presupposes no further innate ground (or preformation). This view will have important consequences for issues such as the ground of the normativity of logical rules and the boundaries of their rightful use
Between Du Châteletâs Leibniz Exegesis and Kantâs Early Philosophy: A Study of Their Responses to the vis viva Controversy
This paper examines Du Châteletâs and Kantâs responses to the famous vis viva controversy â
Du Châtelet in her Institutions Physiques (1742) and Kant in his debut, the Thoughts on the
True Estimation of Living Forces (1746â49). The Institutions was not only a highly influential
contribution to the vis viva controversy, but also a pioneering attempt to integrate Leibnizian
metaphysics and Newtonian physics. The young Kantâs evident knowledge of this work has
led some to speculate about his indebtedness to her philosophy. My study corrects such
speculations as well as misunderstandings of the Living Forces. This corrective result has
implications for how to investigate Kantâs relation to the ever-evolving landscape of Leibniz
exegeses
Kant and the Principle of Sufficient Reason
Leibniz, and many following him, saw the Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR) as pivotal to a scientific (demonstrated) metaphysics. Against this backdrop, Kant is expected to pay close attention to PSR in his reflections on the possibility of metaphysics, which is his chief concern in the Critique of Pure Reason. It is far from clear, however, what has become of PSR in the Critique. On one reading, Kant has simply turned it into the causal principle of the Second Analogy. On a different reading, PSR is but the supreme principle of reason, which roughly states that, if the conditioned is given, so is the unconditioned. On my reading, PSR appears in the guises of both the causal principle and the supreme principle. This twofold specification, I argue, is key to understanding (i) Kantâs allegations that past metaphysicians failed to prove PSR, (ii) his own Critical account of the possibility of metaphysics in both of its parts (ontology and metaphysics proper), and (iii) his nuanced answer to the contentious question about the relation between physical inquiry and metaphysical reasoning about nature (both being quests for reasons)
Know Your Place, Know Your Calling: Geography, Race, and Kantâs âWorld-Citizenâ
Anthropology and physical geography were among Kantâs most popular and longest running courses. He intended them to give his students the world-knowledge (WeltkenntniĂ) that they needed in order to be effective world-citizens (WeltbĂźrgern). Much of this indoctrination amounted to teaching Occidental white men, Kantâs default audience, to perceive themselves as uniquely entitled and obliged to work as agents of human progress on the assumption that they, thanks to their geographic location on Earth, were naturally formed as an exceptional race. I trace this perception to a combination of Kantâs lectures and publications. He already indicated it in some of his works from the 1750s and 1760s. He subsequently fleshed it out through a theory of race based on his geography course in conjunction with a pure moral theory, a pragmatic anthropology that complements the moral theory, and a theory of education that builds on those three
RON: Reverse Connection with Objectness Prior Networks for Object Detection
We present RON, an efficient and effective framework for generic object
detection. Our motivation is to smartly associate the best of the region-based
(e.g., Faster R-CNN) and region-free (e.g., SSD) methodologies. Under fully
convolutional architecture, RON mainly focuses on two fundamental problems: (a)
multi-scale object localization and (b) negative sample mining. To address (a),
we design the reverse connection, which enables the network to detect objects
on multi-levels of CNNs. To deal with (b), we propose the objectness prior to
significantly reduce the searching space of objects. We optimize the reverse
connection, objectness prior and object detector jointly by a multi-task loss
function, thus RON can directly predict final detection results from all
locations of various feature maps. Extensive experiments on the challenging
PASCAL VOC 2007, PASCAL VOC 2012 and MS COCO benchmarks demonstrate the
competitive performance of RON. Specifically, with VGG-16 and low resolution
384X384 input size, the network gets 81.3% mAP on PASCAL VOC 2007, 80.7% mAP on
PASCAL VOC 2012 datasets. Its superiority increases when datasets become larger
and more difficult, as demonstrated by the results on the MS COCO dataset. With
1.5G GPU memory at test phase, the speed of the network is 15 FPS, 3X faster
than the Faster R-CNN counterpart.Comment: Project page will be available at https://github.com/taokong/RON, and
formal paper will appear in CVPR 201
A Spatiotemporal-chaos-based Encryption Having Overall Properties Considerably Better Than Advanced Encryption Standard
Spatiotemporal chaos of a two-dimensional one-way coupled map lattice is used
for chaotic cryptography. The chaotic outputs of many space units are used for
encryption simultaneously. This system shows satisfactory cryptographic
properties of high security; fast encryption (decryption) speed; and robustness
against noise disturbances in communication channel. The overall features of
this spatiotemporal-chaos-based cryptosystem are better than chaotic
cryptosystems known so far, and also than currently used conventional
cryptosystems, such as the Advanced Encryption Standard (AES).Comment: 11 pages, 3 figure
Kant's Use of Travel Reports in Theorizing about Race -A Case Study of How Testimony Features in Natural Philosophy
A testimony is somebody elseâs reported experience of what has happened. It is an indispensable source of knowledge. It only gives us historical cognition, however, which stands in a complex relation to rational or philosophical cognition: while the latter presupposes historical cognition as its matter, one needs the architectonic âeye of a philosopherâ to select, interpret, and organize historical cognition. Kant develops this rationalist theory of testimony. He also practices it in his own work, especially while theorizing about race as a subject of natural philosophy. In three dedicated essays on this subject, he treats race from the standpoint of a philosophical investigator of nature (Naturforscher), who (as Kant puts it in the first Critique) learns from nature âlike an appointed judge who compels witnesses to answer the questions he puts to them.â This view underwrites Kantâs use of travel reports (a type of testimony) in developing and defending his theory of race
- âŚ