31 research outputs found
Split Cycle: A New Condorcet Consistent Voting Method Independent of Clones and Immune to Spoilers
We propose a Condorcet consistent voting method that we call Split Cycle.
Split Cycle belongs to the small family of known voting methods that
significantly narrow the choice of winners in the presence of majority cycles
while also satisfying independence of clones. In this family, only Split Cycle
satisfies a new criterion we call immunity to spoilers, which concerns adding
candidates to elections, as well as the known criteria of positive involvement
and negative involvement, which concern adding voters to elections. Thus, in
contrast to other clone-independent methods, Split Cycle mitigates both
"spoiler effects" and "strong no show paradoxes."Comment: 71 pages, 15 figures. Added a new explanation of Split Cycle in
Section 1, updated the caption to Figure 2, the discussion in Section 3.3,
and Remark 4.11, and strengthened Proposition 6.20 to Theorem 6.20 to cover
single-voter resolvability in addition to asymptotic resolvability. Thanks to
Nicolaus Tideman for helpful discussio
Complete Additivity and Modal Incompleteness
In this paper, we tell a story about incompleteness in modal logic. The story
weaves together a paper of van Benthem, `Syntactic aspects of modal
incompleteness theorems,' and a longstanding open question: whether every
normal modal logic can be characterized by a class of completely additive modal
algebras, or as we call them, V-BAOs. Using a first-order reformulation of the
property of complete additivity, we prove that the modal logic that starred in
van Benthem's paper resolves the open question in the negative. In addition,
for the case of bimodal logic, we show that there is a naturally occurring
logic that is incomplete with respect to V-BAOs, namely the provability logic
GLB. We also show that even logics that are unsound with respect to such
algebras do not have to be more complex than the classical propositional
calculus. On the other hand, we observe that it is undecidable whether a
syntactically defined logic is V-complete. After these results, we generalize
the Blok Dichotomy to degrees of V-incompleteness. In the end, we return to van
Benthem's theme of syntactic aspects of modal incompleteness
A fundamental non-classical logic
We give a proof-theoretic as well as a semantic characterization of a logic
in the signature with conjunction, disjunction, negation, and the universal and
existential quantifiers that we suggest has a certain fundamental status. We
present a Fitch-style natural deduction system for the logic that contains only
the introduction and elimination rules for the logical constants. From this
starting point, if one adds the rule that Fitch called Reiteration, one obtains
a proof system for intuitionistic logic in the given signature; if instead of
adding Reiteration, one adds the rule of Reductio ad Absurdum, one obtains a
proof system for orthologic; by adding both Reiteration and Reductio, one
obtains a proof system for classical logic. Arguably neither Reiteration nor
Reductio is as intimately related to the meaning of the connectives as the
introduction and elimination rules are, so the base logic we identify serves as
a more fundamental starting point and common ground between proponents of
intuitionistic logic, orthologic, and classical logic. The algebraic semantics
for the logic we motivate proof-theoretically is based on bounded lattices
equipped with what has been called a weak pseudocomplementation. We show that
such lattice expansions are representable using a set together with a reflexive
binary relation satisfying a simple first-order condition, which yields an
elegant relational semantics for the logic. This builds on our previous study
of representations of lattices with negations, which we extend and specialize
for several types of negation in addition to weak pseudocomplementation; in an
appendix, we further extend this representation to lattices with implications.
Finally, we discuss adding to our logic a conditional obeying only introduction
and elimination rules, interpreted as a modality using a family of
accessibility relations.Comment: added topological representation of bounded lattices with
implications in Appendi
An impossibility theorem concerning positive involvement in voting
In social choice theory with ordinal preferences, a voting method satisfies
the axiom of positive involvement if adding to a preference profile a voter who
ranks an alternative uniquely first cannot cause that alternative to go from
winning to losing. In this note, we prove a new impossibility theorem
concerning this axiom: there is no ordinal voting method satisfying positive
involvement that also satisfies the Condorcet winner and loser criteria,
resolvability, and a common invariance property for Condorcet methods, namely
that the choice of winners depends only on the ordering of majority margins by
size
Indicative Conditionals and Dynamic Epistemic Logic
Recent ideas about epistemic modals and indicative conditionals in formal
semantics have significant overlap with ideas in modal logic and dynamic
epistemic logic. The purpose of this paper is to show how greater interaction
between formal semantics and dynamic epistemic logic in this area can be of
mutual benefit. In one direction, we show how concepts and tools from modal
logic and dynamic epistemic logic can be used to give a simple, complete
axiomatization of Yalcin's [16] semantic consequence relation for a language
with epistemic modals and indicative conditionals. In the other direction, the
formal semantics for indicative conditionals due to Kolodny and MacFarlane [9]
gives rise to a new dynamic operator that is very natural from the point of
view of dynamic epistemic logic, allowing succinct expression of dependence (as
in dependence logic) or supervenience statements. We prove decidability for the
logic with epistemic modals and Kolodny and MacFarlane's indicative conditional
via a full and faithful computable translation from their logic to the modal
logic K45.Comment: In Proceedings TARK 2017, arXiv:1707.0825
Axioms for Defeat in Democratic Elections
We propose six axioms concerning when one candidate should defeat another in
a democratic election involving two or more candidates. Five of the axioms are
widely satisfied by known voting procedures. The sixth axiom is a weakening of
Kenneth Arrow's famous condition of the Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives
(IIA). We call this weakening Coherent IIA. We prove that the five axioms plus
Coherent IIA single out a voting procedure studied in our recent work: Split
Cycle. In particular, Split Cycle is the most resolute voting procedure
satisfying the six axioms for democratic defeat. In addition, we analyze how
Split Cycle escapes Arrow's Impossibility Theorem and related impossibility
results.Comment: 41 page
Impossibility theorems involving weakenings of expansion consistency and resoluteness in voting
A fundamental principle of individual rational choice is Sen's
axiom, also known as expansion consistency, stating that any alternative chosen
from each of two menus must be chosen from the union of the menus. Expansion
consistency can also be formulated in the setting of social choice. In voting
theory, it states that any candidate chosen from two fields of candidates must
be chosen from the combined field of candidates. An important special case of
the axiom is binary expansion consistency, which states that any candidate
chosen from an initial field of candidates and chosen in a head-to-head match
with a new candidate must also be chosen when the new candidate is added to the
field, thereby ruling out spoiler effects. In this paper, we study the tension
between this weakening of expansion consistency and weakenings of resoluteness,
an axiom demanding the choice of a single candidate in any election. As is well
known, resoluteness is inconsistent with basic fairness conditions on social
choice, namely anonymity and neutrality. Here we prove that even significant
weakenings of resoluteness, which are consistent with anonymity and neutrality,
are inconsistent with binary expansion consistency. The proofs make use of SAT
solving, with the correctness of a SAT encoding formally verified in the Lean
Theorem Prover, as well as a strategy for generalizing impossibility theorems
obtained for special types of voting methods (namely majoritarian and pairwise
voting methods) to impossibility theorems for arbitrary voting methods. This
proof strategy may be of independent interest for its potential applicability
to other impossibility theorems in social choice.Comment: Forthcoming in Mathematical Analyses of Decisions, Voting, and Games,
eds. M. A. Jones, D. McCune, and J. Wilson, Contemporary Mathematics,
American Mathematical Society, 202
The Orthologic of Epistemic Modals
Epistemic modals have peculiar logical features that are challenging to
account for in a broadly classical framework. For instance, while a sentence of
the form (', but it might be that not ') appears
to be a contradiction, does not entail , which would
follow in classical logic. Likewise, the classical laws of distributivity and
disjunctive syllogism fail for epistemic modals. Existing attempts to account
for these facts generally either under- or over-correct. Some predict that
, a so-called epistemic contradiction, is a
contradiction only in an etiolated sense, under a notion of entailment that
does not always allow us to replace with a
contradiction; these theories underpredict the infelicity of embedded epistemic
contradictions. Other theories savage classical logic, eliminating not just
rules that intuitively fail but also rules like non-contradiction, excluded
middle, De Morgan's laws, and disjunction introduction, which intuitively
remain valid for epistemic modals. In this paper, we aim for a middle ground,
developing a semantics and logic for epistemic modals that makes epistemic
contradictions genuine contradictions and that invalidates distributivity and
disjunctive syllogism but that otherwise preserves classical laws that
intuitively remain valid. We start with an algebraic semantics, based on
ortholattices instead of Boolean algebras, and then propose a more concrete
possibility semantics, based on partial possibilities related by compatibility.
Both semantics yield the same consequence relation, which we axiomatize. Then
we show how to extend our semantics to explain parallel phenomena involving
probabilities and conditionals. The goal throughout is to retain what is
desirable about classical logic while accounting for the non-classicality of
epistemic vocabulary.Comment: added Lemma 3.27, Fact 3.30, Definition 4.36, and Remark 4.3