508 research outputs found
Sufficient Reason and the Causal Argument for Monism
What is the role of the principle of sufficient reason in
Baruch Spinozaâs ontological proof for Godâs existence? Is this role
identical within Spinozaâs early work on method, the Treatise on the
Emendation of the Intellect, and his magnum opus, the Ethics? This paper
argues affirmatively that the methodology employed within the Ethics is
consonant with that method found within the Treatise, and this claim is
substantiated through an engagement with the influential works of Don
Garrett and Aaron Garrett. It is also demonstrated through an original
reconstruction of the Treatise itself. In this reconstruction, basic premises
are identified which can validly prove Spinozaâs intended conclusion of
substance monism. It is finally determined that what the Treatise and the
Ethics share, specifically, is a methodology which begins with non-nominal
definitions that denote the real, sufficient causes of their respective objects.
However, at certain junctures, this methodology is expressed with greater
consistency within the Treatise as opposed to within the Ethics. Evidence for
this will be provided from the primary texts themselves and from the
subsequent analyses of Don Garrett and Aaron Garret as well
Aliens, Antisemitism, and Academia
Alt-right conspiracy theorists have embraced postmodern philosophy. The Left
should return to the Enlightenment to oppose their irrational and hateful politics
Impartiality or OikeiĂŽsis?
âUniversal benevolenceâ may be defined as the goal of promoting the welfare of every individual, however remote, to the best of oneâs ability. Currently, the commonest model of universal benevolence is that of âimpartiality,â the notion promoted by Peter Singer, Roderick Firth, and others, that every individual (including oneself) is of equal intrinsic worth. This paper contends that the impartialist model is seriously flawed. Specifically, it is demonstrated that impartialist accounts of benevolence (1) attempt to draw positive moral conclusions from negative premises, (2) draw actual conclusions from merely counterfactual premises, (3) fail to live up to stated claims of naturalism, and (4) give no compelling account of moral motivation. By contrast, I propose an alternate model of universal benevolence, grounded in the Stoic, cosmopolitan theory of oikeiĂŽsis, i.e. âappropriation.â Such a model, in contradistinction to impartiality, would see benevolence as the positive identification between moral agent and moral patient, rather than a charitable sacrifice of oneself for a distinct but equal other. An ethics of oikeiĂŽsis has the further benefit of avoiding each of the four abovementioned conceptual pitfalls common to impartialist theories
Should the State Teach Ethics? A Schematism
Should the state teach ethics? There is widespread disagreement on whether (and how) secular states should be in the business of promoting a particular moral viewpoint. This article attempts to schematize, and evaluate, these stances. It does so by posing three, simple questions: (1) Should the state explicitly promote certain ethical values over others? (2) Should the state have ultimate justifications for the values it promotes? (3) Should the state compel its citizens to accept these ultimate justifications? Logically, each question in this series is a prerequisite for considering those questions further down the list. The result is that responses can be categorized into one of four possible permutations or âcamps.â These are: (1) The Libertarian (âNoâ to all three questions) (2) The Pluralist (âYesâ to question 1; âNoâ to questions 2 and 3) (3) The Rationalist Republican (âYesâ to questions 1 and 2; âNoâ to question 3) (4) The Rigorous Republican (âYesâ to all three questions) It will be shown that just one of these positions, the ârationalist republican,â stands out from all the rest. For only the rationalist republican can account for a normative politics while also safeguarding the individualâs freedom of conscience
Dialectical Enlightenment
A revolt against the Enlightenmentâs legacy has marked the academic culture of a
generation. Leftists today often criticize the Radical Enlightenment thesis,
arguing that those who advance it privilege the force of ideas in history over
material forces. They accuse its proponents of elevating philosophy written by
elite European men over the sacrifices made by ordinary people in the course of
mass struggle
Reason is Red: Why Marxism Needs Philosophy
Landon Frim and Harrison Flussâs following article, âReason is Red: Why Marxism Needs Philosophyâ is a response to Aaron Jaffeâs, âMarxism, Spinoza, and the âRadicalâ Enlightenment.'
Itâs not that activism is of second-rate import. Itâs that something as important as intervening in the world, and affecting peopleâs lives, requires sound justification. If we are committed to âthe ideaâ of communism, then weâre also committed to its practical realization and all of the real-world consequences that this entails. Being serious about ideas means confronting their flesh-and-blood impacts when they come to fruition. Intellectual maturity, then, demands an accounting of our political ideals. We have to care that we are right and that our enemies are wrong. And this means something more than being on the âright sideâ of a particular issue; it means knowing that your politics are grounded in an accurate conception of reality and of what is objectively good for human beings
Steven Pinker: False Friend of the Enlightenment
Steven Pinker's technocratic liberalism has nothing to do with the radical spirit of the
Enlightenment:
Steven Pinkerâs Enlightenment Now is a manual for liberal self-congratulation. This
preening tome professes a pragmatic and quantitative approach to the worldâs
problems. For Pinker, modern capitalist democracy has basically gotten things
right, and activism should at most consist of pushing for minor improvements,
mitigating bad symptoms around the edges
- âŠ