26 research outputs found
Group Virtues: No Great Leap Forward with Collectivism
A body of work in ethics and epistemology has advanced a collectivist view of virtues. Collectivism holds that some social groups can be subjects in themselves which can possess attributes such as agency or responsibility. Collectivism about virtues holds that virtues (and vices) are among those attributes. By focusing on two different accounts, I argue that the collectivist virtue project has limited prospects. On one such interpretation of institutional virtues, virtue-like features of the social collective are explained by particular group-oriented features of individual role-bearers that are elicited by institutional structures or goals. On another account of groups as moral agents unbound by formal institutional constraints, to the extent that group characteristics meet the collectivist requirement, they fail to stand up as virtues in the substantive sense of a character trait. These two positions’ respective drawbacks and insights support a non-collectivist conclusion: Where there is a substantive virtue of some social group, it consists only in certain group-specific attitudes and motives of individuals qua members of that group. I end by outlining some risks in adopting collectivism about virtues as an explanatory or normative doctrine, and suggesting that we can abandon it without embracing an equally undesirable individualism in virtue theory
Recommended from our members
Predicating from an early age: edusemiotics and the potential of children’s preconceptions
This paper aims to explain how semiotics and constructivism can collaborate in an educational epistemology by developing a joint approach to prescientific conceptions. Empirical data and findings of constructivist research are interpreted in the light of Peirce’s semiotics. Peirce’s semiotics is an anti-psychologistic logic (CP 2.252; CP 4.551; W 8:15; Pietarinen in Signs of logic, Springer, Dordrecht, 2006; Stjernfelt in Diagrammatology. An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology and semiotics, Springer, Dordrecht, 2007) and relational logic. Constructivism was traditionally developed within psychology and sociology and, therefore, some incompatibilities can be expected between these two schools. While acknowledging the differences, we explain that constructivism and semiotics share the assumption of realism that knowledge can only be developed upon knowledge and, therefore, an epistemological collaboration is possible. The semiotic analysis performed confirms the constructivist results and provides a further insight into the teacher-student relation. Like the constructivist approach, Peirce’s doctrine of agapism infers that the personal dimension of teaching must not be ignored. Thus, we argue for the importance of genuine sympathy in teaching attitudes. More broadly, the article also contributes to the development of postmodern humanities. At the end of the modern age, the humanities are passing through a critical period of transformation. There is a growing interest in semiotics and semiotic philosophy in many areas of the humanities. Such a case, on which we draw, is the development of a theoretical semiotic approach to education, namely edusemiotics (Stables and Semetsky, Pedagogy and edusemiotics: theoretical challenge/practical opportunities, Sense Publishers, Rotterdam, 2015)
Educação científica na perspectiva de letramento como prática social: funções, princípios e desafios
Enseñanza de las ciencias : revista de investigación y experiencias didácticas
Resumen basado en el de la publicaciónResumen en inglésLas diferencias entre las ideas de los niños y el pensamiento científico nos dan alguna indicación de los tipos de cambios y la magnitud de estos que se intentan promover en la comprensión de los jóvenes
durante los años escolares. Se revisa cómo se pueden promover dichos cambios y se considera las implicaciones para la planificación curricular.ES
Enseñanza de las ciencias : revista de investigación y experiencias didácticas
Resumen basado en el de la publicaciónResumen en inglésEn primer lugar se presenta una visión general de la investigación que ha sido emprendida en base a las concepciones de los estudiantes relacionadas con la mecánica. Una característica central de la "mecánica intuitiva" de los estudiantes es la asociación entre sus nociones de fuerza y movimiento. Se describen las consecuencias de tales ideas en el razonamiento de los estudiantes sobre varios sistemas estáticos y dinámicos. A continuación, se describen una serie de características generales de las concepciones alternativas de los estudiantes. posteriormente se describen las perspectivas actuales sobre el aprendizaje con particular énfasis en la perspectiva constructivista; una perspectiva que enfatiza el rol activo de los estudiantes en la construcción de su conocimiento. Finalmente se describen las consecuencias pedagógicas de adoptar esta perspectiva.ES
Establishing the norms of scientific argumentation in classrooms
Basing its arguments in current perspectives on the nature of the scientific enterprise, which see argument and argumentative practice as a core activity of scientists, this article develops the case for the inclusion and central role of argument in science education. Beginning with a review of the nature of argument, it discusses the function and purpose of dialogic argument in the social construction of scientific knowledge and the interpretation of empirical data. The case is then advanced that any education about science, rather than education in science, must give the role of argument a high priority if it is to give a fair account of the social practice of science, and develop a knowledge and understanding of the evaluative criteria used to establish scientific theories. Such knowledge is essential to enhance the public understanding of science and improve scientific literacy. The existing literature, and work that has attempted to use argument within science education, is reviewed to show that classroom practice does provide the opportunity to develop young people's ability to construct argument. Furthermore, the case is advanced that the lack of opportunities for the practice of argument within science classrooms, and lack of teacher's pedagogical skills in organizing argumentative discourse within the classroom are significant impediments to progress in the field. © 2000 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Sci Ed84:287–312, 2000