131 research outputs found

    Bisimilarity is not Borel

    Full text link
    We prove that the relation of bisimilarity between countable labelled transition systems is Σ11\Sigma_1^1-complete (hence not Borel), by reducing the set of non-wellorders over the natural numbers continuously to it. This has an impact on the theory of probabilistic and nondeterministic processes over uncountable spaces, since logical characterizations of bisimilarity (as, for instance, those based on the unique structure theorem for analytic spaces) require a countable logic whose formulas have measurable semantics. Our reduction shows that such a logic does not exist in the case of image-infinite processes.Comment: 20 pages, 1 figure; proof of Sigma_1^1 completeness added with extended comments. I acknowledge careful reading by the referees. Major changes in Introduction, Conclusion, and motivation for NLMP. Proof for Lemma 22 added, simpler proofs for Lemma 17 and Theorem 30. Added references. Part of this work was presented at Dagstuhl Seminar 12411 on Coalgebraic Logic

    Kleisli morphisms and randomized congruences for the Giry monad

    Get PDF
    AbstractStochastic relations are the Kleisli morphisms for the Giry monad. This paper proposes the study of the associated morphisms and congruences. The relationship between kernels of these morphisms and congruences is studied, and a unique factorization of a morphism through this kernel is shown to exist. This study is based on an investigation into countably generated equivalence relations on the space of all subprobabilities. Operations on these relations are investigated quite closely. This utilizes positive convex structures and indicates cross-connections to Eilenberg–Moore algebras for the Giry monad. Hennessy–Milner logic serves as an illustration for randomized morphisms and congruences

    Dynamical systems via domains:Toward a unified foundation of symbolic and non-symbolic computation

    Get PDF
    Non-symbolic computation (as, e.g., in biological and artificial neural networks) is astonishingly good at learning and processing noisy real-world data. However, it lacks the kind of understanding we have of symbolic computation (as, e.g., specified by programming languages). Just like symbolic computation, also non-symbolic computation needs a semantics—or behavior description—to achieve structural understanding. Domain theory has provided this for symbolic computation, and this thesis is about extending it to non-symbolic computation. Symbolic and non-symbolic computation can be described in a unified framework as state-discrete and state-continuous dynamical systems, respectively. So we need a semantics for dynamical systems: assigning to a dynamical system a domain—i.e., a certain mathematical structure—describing the system’s behavior. In part 1 of the thesis, we provide this domain-theoretic semantics for the ‘symbolic’ state-discrete systems (i.e., labeled transition systems). And in part 2, we do this for the ‘non-symbolic’ state-continuous systems (known from ergodic theory). This is a proper semantics in that the constructions form functors (in the sense of category theory) and, once appropriately formulated, even adjunctions and, stronger yet, equivalences. In part 3, we explore how this semantics relates the two types of computation. It suggests that non-symbolic computation is the limit of symbolic computation (in the ‘profinite’ sense). Conversely, if the system’s behavior is fairly stable, it may be described as realizing symbolic computation (here the concepts of ergodicity and algorithmic randomness are useful). However, the underlying concept of stability is limited by a no-go result due to a novel interpretation of Fitch’s paradox. This also has implications for AI-safety and, more generally, suggests fruitful applications of philosophical tools in the non-symbolic computation of modern AI
    • …
    corecore