12 research outputs found

    Regulating Contract Formation: Precontractual Reliance, Sunk Costs, and Market Structure

    Get PDF
    This Article challenges the plausibility of the prospect of underinvestment in precontractual reliance (PCR). We argue that a negotiating party is motivated to invest in PCR not only through her expectation to extract the benefits that the investment yields (Added-Value Motivation), but also through the effect of the investment on her position vis-à-vis her competitors (Competition-Based Motivation). We demonstrate that under plausible assumptions, when a negotiating party operates in a relatively competitive market, the Competition-Based Motivation is frequently sufficient to induce optimal PCR, even without appropriate contractual provisions or legal intervention. We suggest several normative implications. First, legal intervention that is aimed at encouraging PCR is generally unwarranted. The forces of competition provide adequate investment incentives, and the regulation of contract formation should only facilitate their operation. We thus justify the reluctance of both positive law and commercial parties from imposing precontractual liability in cases of failed negotiations. Second, the analysis demonstrates that when one party (e.g., the supplier) operates in a competitive market of “professional” repeating players, the other party (e.g., the purchaser) is better off limiting the number of bidders (suppliers) with whom he negotiates. This result suggests that in such cases, from an efficiency perspective, a party (including a public authority) should be allowed to limit the number of suppliers with whom he conducts negotiations. By contrast, when suppliers operate in a competitive market of accidental, one-time players, the purchaser has an interest in encouraging excessive entry of suppliers into the negotiations, and legal intervention aimed at regulating the purchaser’s behavior can be justified. This result may justify, for instance, imposing a duty on employers to pay for training periods of potential employees. Third, legal intervention is justified in order to prevent manipulation of bidder’s assessment of their prospects to receive the contract. The analysis supports a rule that prohibits an auctioneer from receiving an offer that was submitted outside of the auction’s procedures, and a rule that disallows changing “the rules of the game” after the bidders already invested in PCR. Fourth, we show that when legal intervention is justified in the negotiation stage, the appropriate measure of damages that should be awarded is the plaintiff’s expectation interest. We also demonstrate that the difficulty in assessing this value when a contract is not formed can be resolved by approximating this value according to the sum of PCR for all bidders. Finally, we offer a new rationale for imposing disclosure duties (as well as other mandatory requirements to invest in PCR). We show that, in certain cases, such investment is allocated to the party who operates in a competitive market, even if it is efficient for the other party to bear this cost. Legal intervention is essential in such cases to resolve this inefficiency in the allocation of PCR. We refer in this respect to the case of Laidlaw v. Organ, and demonstrate why imposing a duty to disclose information is not expected to adversely affect a party’s incentive to invest in acquiring information

    Remedies for Wrongfully-Issued Preliminary Injunctions: The Case for Disgorgement of Profits

    Get PDF
    This Article demonstrates that the underlying aim of remedies for wrongfully issued preliminary injuntion leads to two central conclusions. First, it is desirable to award the remedy of restitution, which requires the moving party to disgorge all the benefits obtained at the expense of the defendant as a result of the wrongfully-issued preliminary injunction. Second, it may be unjustified to compel the plaintiff to compensate the defendant for all harms inflicted by the wrongfully-issued preliminary injunction. Part I of this Article summarizes the law of remedies for wrongfully-issued preliminary injunctions. Part I.A surveys the doctrinal reasons for imposing on the moving party only partial liability for the defendant\u27s harms, while Part I.B presents the very limited availability of the remedy of restitution for wrongfully-issued preliminary injunctions under current law. Part II lays the theoretical ground for the analysis. Part II.A discusses the underlying purpose behind issuing a preliminary injunction: the minimization of the irreparable loss of rights resulting from an erroneous assignment of entitlements at the preliminary stage. Part II.B presents the standard for issuing a preliminary injunction. Part II.C analyzes the possible paths by which the remedy for wrongfully-issued preliminary injunctions achieves this aim. Part III deals with the ex-post perspective, and shows that the remedy of restitution is better suited to achieve the aim of minimizing irreparable social harms. Part IV inquires into the role remedies for wrongfully-issued preliminary injunctions play in shaping the parties\u27 incentives in deciding whether to apply for a preliminary injunction, and shows the superiority of the restitutionary remedy in this respect

    Why Do We Know What We Know? Reevaluating the Economic Case against Pre-Contractual Disclosure Duties and for Break-Up Fees

    Get PDF
    The economic analysis of contract law offers influential arguments against pre-contractual disclosure duties and for break-up fees, based on the presumption that pre-contractual duties are (or should be) set to provide sufficient incentives to optimally invest in acquiring information at the negotiation stage. We suggest, however, that the existing analysis is flawed, since it overlooks an important incentive for investing in information gathering. According to the conventional wisdom, a negotiating party will be motivated to invest resources in information gathering only on the basis of its expectation to extract the contractual surplus that the investment may generate. As a result, it is arguably essential to protect the investing party’s ability to benefit from its investment (by allowing non-disclosure) or to strengthen its bargaining position by guaranteeing reimbursement for the investment (break-up fees). However, contracting parties (e.g., the purchaser) invest resources in acquiring information not only—and probably not even primarily—to strengthen its bargaining position vis-à-vis its counterpart (e.g., the seller). Rather, the investment in acquiring information is often aimed at achieving an advantage vis-à-vis its competitors (e.g., other potential purchasers of the same asset), endeavoring to increase the investing party’s likelihood of forming a contract. Thus, even if the seller is able to extract all the contractual surplus generated by the investment, potential purchasers may well find it beneficial to invest in acquiring information to gain a competitive edge toward sealing a deal. In layman’s terms: a negotiator may invest in gathering information not only for the hope of sweetening the deal for herself, but also for the prospect of being able to submit a better offer to the other party. As a result, the argument of the existing literature against imposing a duty to disclose information and in favor of reimbursement provisions cannot be substantiated without a careful inquiry into competition-based motivations to gather information. Specifically, the analysis yields that, among other things, the exemption from disclosure cannot be justified on efficiency grounds in case of information that players in the relevant market regularly collect (e.g., examining the property that is offered for sale or interviewing potential job candidates). The competition-based motivation is insufficient, and legal protection is justified, only in the case of “exceptional” deliberately acquired information (e.g., searching for oil reserves or conducting a thorough job-screening through an extensive training program)

    Rationalizing Drennan: On Irrevocable Offers, Bid Shopping and Binding Range

    No full text
    Courts may determine that an offer is irrevocable due to the offerees reasonable reliance on it. For instance, the landmark case of Drennan v. Star Paving Co. (1958) held a subcontractors price offer to be irrevocable once it had been relied upon by the general contractor in computing his overall bid. However, a rule of implied irrevocability raises two main difficulties. First, it seems unfair to force the offeror to commit, but not the offeree. Second, from an ex ante perspective, the implied irrevocability rule seems to deter parties from submitting low-priced, unqualified offers. These concerns have led several scholars to argue for modification of the rule. This paper rationalizes the implied irrevocability rule by demonstrating that the above concerns are unfounded. We demonstrate that whereas some restrictions on the offerees freedom to conduct bid shopping ex post (i.e., after the uncertainties are resolved) are essential in order to allow him to receive viable price offers ex ante, these restrictions need not be absolute nor legally enforced. Partial restrictions, in the form of a self-enforced Binding Range, may well suffice. The plausible existence of a self-enforced Binding Range ensures that offerors have incentives to submit irrevocable bids because they can expect to earn a profit by submitting the best offer. This paper characterizes the optimal size of the Binding Range, and explores what legal provisions should be applied when the self-enforced Binding Range is sub-optimal.
    corecore