109 research outputs found
Preface to an ethics of education as a practice in its own right
Education as a practice in its own right (or sui generis practice) invokes
quite a different set of ethical considerations than does education
understood as a subordinate activity – i.e. prescribed and controlled in
its essentials by the current powers-that-be in a society. But the idea of
education as a vehicle for the ‘values’ of a particular group or party is so
commonplace, from history’s legacy as well as from ongoing waves of
educational reforms, as to appear a quite natural one. So much is this case
that the idea of education as a sui generis practice may seem a bit eccentric
at first sight. Some preliminary work is called for then to render intelligible
the claim that education is indeed a practice in its own right, and to
illustrate the original starting point this gives for an exploration of
educational ethics. In undertaking this preliminary work, central themes
from two major sources are explored and reviewed: Richard Peters’ wellknown
study Ethics and education and MacIntyre’s After virtue. The
suggestive merits of both works for advancing a sui generis understanding
of education and its conduct are identified. But crucial occlusions are also
highlighted in the arguments of both authors, the recognition of which
might have enabled their thinking on educational matters to venture onto a
different plane. The kind of thinking that emerges from these investigations
as most promising for educational ethics is seen to differ in its key features
from what the various branches of academic philosophy have to offer by
way of ethical theory
Schooling, Religious Tradition and the Default of God
To the contemporary reader the phrase 'the default of God' may suggest something shocking, such as a failure on God's part to keep a bargain or a promise. Accordingly, it may seem a curious imper tinence to make this 'default' an explicit theme in an essay on religious tradition and education. It is important therefore, at the outset, to secure the theme as far as possible against misunderstanding. Default here signifies 'to be wanting', or 'to be in want of, or 'to be deprived of. Hence, what is described as 'the default of God' is a human, historical event and, as such, it means, in Heidegger's words: 'that no god any longer gathers men and things unto himself, visibly and unequivocably, and by such gather ing disposes the world's history and man's sojourn in it.' Of course a relationship with God continues to live on in our own historical epoch, in individuals, in churches, in some homes and indeed within some schools
A Critique of Educational Research
In an article entitled 'The psychologist's contribution to educational research' Professors J. D. Nisbet & N. J. Entwistle begin by surveying briefly different definitions educational research itself with a view to drawing a distinction between "pure research the social sciences and educational research in the area of the applied sciences" Having suggested this distinction the authors clearly favour a definition which would remove educational research from the category of pure to that of applied research accordingly, their own definition states that "educational research consists in careful, systematic attempts to understand the educational process and, through understanding, improve its efficiency". Pursuing the consequences for educational enquiry of definition they themselves outline, Nisbet & Entwistle point out that this shift in emphasis from 'understanding' to 'improvement' is likely to be dis- puted by many who are active in what they claim to be wholly respectable educational research which does not aim at 'improvement'-such as historical studies and comparative education
Beyond the Habitual Paths of Reasoning
The phrase in the title comes from a passage on page 150 of Thinking Again.
Employed by the authors in the course of an engagement with works of Kierkegaard
and Derrida, it is also an apt phrase to give a suggestive summary of one of the chief
themes in the book as a whole. The theme I have in mind here is really a twofold
one: firstly, the book’s critique-largely an unsympathetic one-of those paths of
reasoning associated with the modernist legacies of the Enlightenment and their
educational embodiments; secondly its critique-a more sympathetic one-of postmodern
moves to abandon the grand ideals and universalistic pretensions of the
Enlightenment’s legacies. In this short contribution to the symposium I will concentrate
on these two critiques
The Question of Ethos in Schools
Interview Board Member: Now Miss Murphy, just one final question. I suppose you are aware that there has been a lot of talk recently about the values and ethos of a school and the need for teachers employed in the school to reflect that ethos in their lifestyle. What is your own view on this whole question? Miss Murphy: Hm . . . well . . . Can I be frank? Interview Board Member: By all means, please do! Miss Murphy: / think it's an exceptionally complex question. As I see it, the school authorities have long standing rights which must be taken seriously and parents too have very important rights which are enshrined in our Constitution. But teachers and pupils also have rights which must be taken seriously and if this is the case then neither the rights of the parents nor of the school authorities are absolute. In other words, what I'm trying to say is that there is no easy answer to the question, but there is a clear need for the various parties to sit down and attempt to thrash out in open discussion some kind of code; the kind of code which might win a substantial and genuine commitment among the parties. Otherwise I think we have a recipe for smouldering dissatisfaction and recurring conflict. The real losers then are the pupils. I think they're very quick to sense the slightest tension in the atmosphere. Interview Board Member: I see! SOME PREVAILING CONCEPTIONS OF ETHOS. I shall begin by asking the reader to consider whether Miss Murphy's forthrightness and style of argument should help in securing for her the post for which she was a candidate or whether her remarks identify her as a potential troublemaker of whom a prudent school management should be wary. The reader may well reply that the information
supplied is too slight to provide the basis for a valid judgement. I am
quite aware of this and I should stress that there is no attempt here to
force the reader prematurely to nail his or her colours publicly to the
mast
A Critique of Educational Research
In an article entitled 'The psychologist's contribution to educational research' Professors J. D. Nisbet & N. J. Entwistle begin by surveying briefly different definitions educational research itself with a view to drawing a distinction between "pure research the social sciences and educational research in the area of the applied sciences" Having suggested this distinction the authors clearly favour a definition which would remove educational research from the category of pure to that of applied research accordingly, their own definition states that "educational research consists in careful, systematic attempts to understand the educational process and, through understanding, improve its efficiency". Pursuing the consequences for educational enquiry of definition they themselves outline, Nisbet & Entwistle point out that this shift in emphasis from 'understanding' to 'improvement' is likely to be dis- puted by many who are active in what they claim to be wholly respectable educational research which does not aim at 'improvement'-such as historical studies and comparative education
The ethical orientations of education as a practice in its own right
This article is the second of a two-part investigation, the first part of which
was published in Ethics and Education, vol. 5, issue 2, 2010, under the title
‘Preface to an ethics of education as a practice in its own right’. Although it
builds on the arguments of that ‘preface’, this second part of the
investigation can be read as a stand-alone essay. It begins with a brief
review of a new subordination of educational practice achieved by a neoliberal
tenor in international educational reforms in recent decades in
Western societies. The practical context for the essay however is that failure
of many of these reforms, like the failure of neo-liberal dominance in socioeconomic
policy, has given rise to emergent opportunities where inspirations
for educational debate and policy-making are concerned. Arguing for
the uptake of such opportunity, the ethical tenor of education as a practice
in its own right is explored under four headings: (1) review and clarification
of the inherent purposes of education as a practice; (2) investigation of
educationally productive pathways that are characteristic of education as a
practice in its own right; (3) elucidation of a recognisable family of virtues
that arise from that practice itself; (4) exploration of the kinds of
relationships through which these virtues, and their educational fruits,
are nourished
Recovering the Lost Métier of Philosophy of Education? Reflections on Educational Thought, Policy and Practice in the UK and Farther Afield
A Special Issue of the Journal of Philosophy of Education in
November 2012 explored key aspects of the relationship
between philosophy of education and educational policy in
the UK. The contributions were generally critical of policy
developments in recent decades, highlighting important
shortcomings and arguing for more philosophically coherent
approaches to educational policy-making. This article begins
by focusing on what the contributions to the Special
Issue—particularly two of them—have to say about the
relationship between philosophy of education and
educational policymaking. It then goes on to argue that this
relationship can best be understood through an exploration
of education as a practice in its own right (as distinct from a
subordinate practice). Such an exploration seeks to shed
light on the proper métier of philosophy of education. In the
course of the exploration the kind of thinking predominant in
recent international patterns in educational policy is
contrasted with a different kind of thinking which has yielded
rich gains in Finland. Important distinctions are drawn
between the inherent and extrinsic benefits of educational
practice and between the internal and external politics of
practice. These contribute to the articulation of philosophy of
education as a distinctive discipline of thought and action
which is necessary to the work of practitioners and
policymakers alike
Beyond the Habitual Paths of Reasoning
The phrase in the title comes from a passage on page 150 of Thinking Again.
Employed by the authors in the course of an engagement with works of Kierkegaard
and Derrida, it is also an apt phrase to give a suggestive summary of one of the chief
themes in the book as a whole. The theme I have in mind here is really a twofold
one: firstly, the book’s critique-largely an unsympathetic one-of those paths of
reasoning associated with the modernist legacies of the Enlightenment and their
educational embodiments; secondly its critique-a more sympathetic one-of postmodern
moves to abandon the grand ideals and universalistic pretensions of the
Enlightenment’s legacies. In this short contribution to the symposium I will concentrate
on these two critiques
School Patronage, Educational Experience and Religious Teachings
There’s an important distinction to be made between how religious teachings are
introduced in a church, mosque or synagogue, and how such teachings are to be introduced
in schools. Where this difference is overlooked there is a danger that the need to distinguish
between educational experience and faith formation will be similarly disregarded. Both
generally involve systematic learning. And religious teachings can feature in both. But
properly understood, educational experience is mainly exploratory in character while faith
formation is, from the start, evangelising in purpose and in practice
- …