434 research outputs found
Reconstructing the trajectory of the August 1680 hurricane from contemporary records
This paper draws on a range of contemporary documentary evidence from the New and Old Worlds as well as from the oceanic regions to reconstruct the trajectory and intensity of an Atlantic hurricane from August 1680. In doing so, it offers the example of one of the earliest and most comprehensive hurricane reconstructions thus far attempted. The source material includes evidence from land-based observers and some of the earliest examples of instrumental barometric data from the Caribbean and from Europe; importantly, it also calls on the written accounts offered in ships' logbooks from various parts of the Atlantic. The latter provide the opportunity of tracking the system across the otherwise data-deficient areas of the North Atlantic as it recurved toward Europe. The findings are of intrinsic interest in documenting a notable historical event. They also offer a methodological model of how such a variety of documentary sources can be drawn together and used to identify, track, and reconstruct such events from the distant past and thereby improve the chronology of hurricanes and make more reliable our interpretation of their changing frequencies
Introduction to Loop Quantum Gravity
This article is based on the opening lecture at the third quantum geometry
and quantum gravity school sponsored by the European Science Foundation and
held at Zakopane, Poland in March 2011. The goal of the lecture was to present
a broad perspective on loop quantum gravity for young researchers. The first
part is addressed to beginning students and the second to young researchers who
are already working in quantum gravity.Comment: 30 pages, 2 figures. arXiv admin note: substantial text overlap with
arXiv:gr-qc/041005
Towards a formal description of the collapse approach to the inflationary origin of the seeds of cosmic structure
Inflation plays a central role in our current understanding of the universe.
According to the standard viewpoint, the homogeneous and isotropic mode of the
inflaton field drove an early phase of nearly exponential expansion of the
universe, while the quantum fluctuations (uncertainties) of the other modes
gave rise to the seeds of cosmic structure. However, if we accept that the
accelerated expansion led the universe into an essentially homogeneous and
isotropic space-time, with the state of all the matter fields in their vacuum
(except for the zero mode of the inflaton field), we can not escape the
conclusion that the state of the universe as a whole would remain always
homogeneous and isotropic. It was recently proposed in [A. Perez, H. Sahlmann
and D. Sudarsky, "On the quantum origin of the seeds of cosmic structure,"
Class. Quant. Grav. 23, 2317-2354 (2006)] that a collapse (representing physics
beyond the established paradigm, and presumably associated with a
quantum-gravity effect a la Penrose) of the state function of the inflaton
field might be the missing element, and thus would be responsible for the
emergence of the primordial inhomogeneities. Here we will discuss a formalism
that relies strongly on quantum field theory on curved space-times, and within
which we can implement a detailed description of such a process. The picture
that emerges clarifies many aspects of the problem, and is conceptually quite
transparent. Nonetheless, we will find that the results lead us to argue that
the resulting picture is not fully compatible with a purely geometric
description of space-time.Comment: 53 pages, no figures. Revision to match the published versio
Physics in the Real Universe: Time and Spacetime
The Block Universe idea, representing spacetime as a fixed whole, suggests
the flow of time is an illusion: the entire universe just is, with no special
meaning attached to the present time. This view is however based on
time-reversible microphysical laws and does not represent macro-physical
behaviour and the development of emergent complex systems, including life,
which do indeed exist in the real universe. When these are taken into account,
the unchanging block universe view of spacetime is best replaced by an evolving
block universe which extends as time evolves, with the potential of the future
continually becoming the certainty of the past. However this time evolution is
not related to any preferred surfaces in spacetime; rather it is associated
with the evolution of proper time along families of world linesComment: 28 pages, including 9 Figures. Major revision in response to referee
comment
The Hamiltonian of Einstein affine-metric formulation of General Relativity
It is shown that the Hamiltonian of the Einstein affine-metric (first order)
formulation of General Relativity (GR) leads to a constraint structure that
allows the restoration of its unique gauge invariance, four-diffeomorphism,
without the need of any field dependent redefinition of gauge parameters as is
the case for the second order formulation. In the second order formulation of
ADM gravity the need for such a redefinition is the result of the non-canonical
change of variables [arXiv: 0809.0097]. For the first order formulation, the
necessity of such a redefinition "to correspond to diffeomorphism invariance"
(reported by Ghalati [arXiv: 0901.3344]) is just an artifact of using the
Henneaux-Teitelboim-Zanelli ansatz [Nucl. Phys. B 332 (1990) 169], which is
sensitive to the choice of linear combination of tertiary constraints. This
ansatz cannot be used as an algorithm for finding a gauge invariance, which is
a unique property of a physical system, and it should not be affected by
different choices of linear combinations of non-primary first class
constraints. The algorithm of Castellani [Ann. Phys. 143 (1982) 357] is free
from such a deficiency and it leads directly to four-diffeomorphism invariance
for first, as well as for second order Hamiltonian formulations of GR. The
distinct role of primary first class constraints, the effect of considering
different linear combinations of constraints, the canonical transformations of
phase-space variables, and their interplay are discussed in some detail for
Hamiltonians of the second and first order formulations of metric GR. The first
order formulation of Einstein-Cartan theory, which is the classical background
of Loop Quantum Gravity, is also discussed.Comment: 74 page
Slowly rotating charged black holes in anti-de Sitter third order Lovelock gravity
In this paper, we study slowly rotating black hole solutions in Lovelock
gravity (n=3). These exact slowly rotating black hole solutions are obtained in
uncharged and charged cases, respectively. Up to the linear order of the
rotating parameter a, the mass, Hawking temperature and entropy of the
uncharged black holes get no corrections from rotation. In charged case, we
compute magnetic dipole moment and gyromagnetic ratio of the black holes. It is
shown that the gyromagnetic ratio keeps invariant after introducing the
Gauss-Bonnet and third order Lovelock interactions.Comment: 14 pages, no figur
The Superspace of Geometrodynamics
Wheeler's Superspace is the arena in which Geometrodynamics takes place. I
review some aspects of its geometrical and topological structure that Wheeler
urged us to take seriously in the context of canonical quantum gravity.Comment: 29 pages, 8 figures. To appear in the Wheeler memorial volume of
General Relativity and Gravitatio
The Hamiltonian formulation of General Relativity: myths and reality
A conventional wisdom often perpetuated in the literature states that: (i) a
3+1 decomposition of space-time into space and time is synonymous with the
canonical treatment and this decomposition is essential for any Hamiltonian
formulation of General Relativity (GR); (ii) the canonical treatment
unavoidably breaks the symmetry between space and time in GR and the resulting
algebra of constraints is not the algebra of four-dimensional diffeomorphism;
(iii) according to some authors this algebra allows one to derive only spatial
diffeomorphism or, according to others, a specific field-dependent and
non-covariant four-dimensional diffeomorphism; (iv) the analyses of Dirac
[Proc. Roy. Soc. A 246 (1958) 333] and of ADM [Arnowitt, Deser and Misner, in
"Gravitation: An Introduction to Current Research" (1962) 227] of the canonical
structure of GR are equivalent. We provide some general reasons why these
statements should be questioned. Points (i-iii) have been shown to be incorrect
in [Kiriushcheva et al., Phys. Lett. A 372 (2008) 5101] and now we thoroughly
re-examine all steps of the Dirac Hamiltonian formulation of GR. We show that
points (i-iii) above cannot be attributed to the Dirac Hamiltonian formulation
of GR. We also demonstrate that ADM and Dirac formulations are related by a
transformation of phase-space variables from the metric to lapse
and shift functions and the three-metric , which is not canonical. This
proves that point (iv) is incorrect. Points (i-iii) are mere consequences of
using a non-canonical change of variables and are not an intrinsic property of
either the Hamilton-Dirac approach to constrained systems or Einstein's theory
itself.Comment: References are added and updated, Introduction is extended,
Subsection 3.5 is added, 83 pages; corresponds to the published versio
- …