291 research outputs found
Towards an atlas of canonical cognitive mechanisms
A central goal in Cognitive Science is understanding the mechanisms that underlie cognition. Here, we contend that Cognitive Science, despite intense multidisciplinary efforts, has furnished surprisingly few mechanistic insights. We attribute this slow mechanistic progress to the fact that cognitive scientists insist on performing underdetermined exercises, deriving overparametrised mechanistic theories of complex behaviours and seeking validation of these theories to the elusive notions of optimality and biological plausibility. We propose that mechanistic progress in Cognitive Science will accelerate once cognitive scientists start focusing on simpler explananda that will enable them to chart an atlas of elementary cognitive operations. Looking forward, the next challenge for Cognitive Science will be to understand how these elementary cognitive processes are pieced together to explain complex behaviour
Building Bridges between Perceptual and Economic Decision-Making: Neural and Computational Mechanisms
Investigation into the neural and computational bases of decision-making has proceeded in two parallel but distinct streams. Perceptual decision-making (PDM) is concerned with how observers detect, discriminate, and categorize noisy sensory information. Economic decision-making (EDM) explores how options are selected on the basis of their reinforcement history. Traditionally, the sub-fields of PDM and EDM have employed different paradigms, proposed different mechanistic models, explored different brain regions, disagreed about whether decisions approach optimality. Nevertheless, we argue that there is a common framework for understanding decisions made in both tasks, under which an agent has to combine sensory information (what is the stimulus) with value information (what is it worth). We review computational models of the decision process typically used in PDM, based around the idea that decisions involve a serial integration of evidence, and assess their applicability to decisions between good and gambles. Subsequently, we consider the contribution of three key brain regions β the parietal cortex, the basal ganglia, and the orbitofrontal cortex (OFC) β to perceptual and EDM, with a focus on the mechanisms by which sensory and reward information are integrated during choice. We find that although the parietal cortex is often implicated in the integration of sensory evidence, there is evidence for its role in encoding the expected value of a decision. Similarly, although much research has emphasized the role of the striatum and OFC in value-guided choices, they may play an important role in categorization of perceptual information. In conclusion, we consider how findings from the two fields might be brought together, in order to move toward a general framework for understanding decision-making in humans and other primates
Information integration in perceptual and value-based decisions
Research on the psychology and neuroscience of simple, evidence-based choices has
led to an impressive progress in capturing the underlying mental processes as optimal
mechanisms that make the fastest decision for a specified accuracy. The idea that
decision-making is an optimal process stands in contrast with findings in more complex,
motivation-based decisions, focussed on multiple goals with trade-offs. Here,
a number of paradoxical and puzzling choice behaviours have been revealed, posing
a serious challenge to the development of a unified theory of choice. These choice
anomalies have been traditionally attributed to oddities at the representation of values
and little is known about the role of the process under which information is integrated
towards a decision. In a series of experiments, by controlling the temporal distribution
of the decision-relevant information (i.e., sensory evidence or value), I demonstrate
that the characteristics of this process cause many puzzling choice paradoxes, such as
temporal, risk and framing biases, as well as preference reversal.
In Chapter 3, I show that information integration is characterized by temporal biases
(Experimental Studies 1-2, Computational Studies 1-3). In Chapter 4, I examine the
way the integration process is affected by the immediate decision context (Experimental
Studies 3-4, Computational Study 4), demonstrating that prior to integration,
the momentary ranking of a sample modifies its magnitude. This principle is further
scrutinized in Chapter 5, where a rank-dependent accumulation model is developed
(Computational Study 5). The rank-dependent model is shown to underlie preference
reversal in multi-attribute choice problems and to predict that choice is sensitive, not
only to the mean strength of the information, but also to its variance, favouring riskier
options (Computational Study 6). This prediction is further confirmed in Chapter 6, in
a number of experiments (Experimental Studies 5-7) while the direction of risk preferences
is found to be modulated by the cognitive perspective induced by the task
framing (Experimental Study 8). I conclude that choice arises from a deliberative process
which gathers samples of decision-relevant information, weighs them according
to their salience and subsequently accumulates them. The salience of a sample is determined
by i) its temporal order and ii) its local ranking in the decision context, while
the direction of the weighting is controlled by the task framing. The implications of
this simple, microprocess model are discussed with respect to choice optimality while
directions for future research, towards the development of a unified theory of choice,
are suggested
ΠΠ΄Π΅ΠΎΠ»ΠΎΠ³ΠΈΡΠ°, ΡΡΠ΄ΡΠΊΠΎΡΡ ΠΈ Π²ΡΠ΅Π΄Π½ΠΎΡΡ. Π ΠΠ΄ΠΎΡΠ½ΠΎΠ²ΠΎΠΌ Π‘ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΎΠΌ
Theodor W. Adornoβs critique of Igor Stravinsky has itself been repeatedly criticised. Following the same line, the present article takes as its point of departure the philosophical anthropology of Helmuth Plessner, which challenges the premises of Marxist anthropology, on which Adorno based his critique of Stravinsky. Far from regressing to the inhuman and primitive, Stravinskyβs music affirms, in historically adequate modern terms, the constitutive reflectivity of the human embodied condition, thus becoming more βhumanβ, i.e. meaningful and expressive, than Adorno could have even conceived. Additionally, an account is provided of some groundbreaking musical qualities that underpin the artistic value of Stravinskyβs music, which Adorno also contested.ΠΠ΄ΠΎΡΠ½ΠΎΠ²Π° ΠΊΡΠΈΡΠΈΠΊΠ° Π‘ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΎΠ³ ΠΈ ΡΠ°ΠΌΠ° ΡΠ΅ ΠΏΡΠ΅ΡΡΠΏΠ΅Π»Π° Π±ΡΠΎΡΠ½Π΅ ΠΊΡΠΈΡΠΈΠΊΠ΅.
ΠΡΠ°ΡΠ΅ΡΠΈ ΡΡ ΠΈΡΡΡ Π»ΠΈΠ½ΠΈΡΡ, ΠΎΠ²Π°Ρ ΡΠ»Π°Π½Π°ΠΊ ΠΊΠ°ΠΎ ΠΏΠΎΠ»Π°Π·ΠΈΡΡΠ΅ ΡΠ·ΠΈΠΌΠ° ΡΠΈΠ»ΠΎΠ·ΠΎΡΡΠΊΡ
Π°Π½ΡΡΠΎΠΏΠΎΠ»ΠΎΠ³ΠΈΡΡ Π₯Π΅Π»ΠΌΡΡΠ° ΠΠ»Π΅ΡΠ½Π΅ΡΠ°, ΠΊΠΎΡΠ° ΠΎΡΠΏΠΎΡΠ°Π²Π° ΠΏΡΠ΅ΠΌΠΈΡΠ΅ ΠΌΠ°ΡΠΊΡΠΈΡΡΠΈΡΠΊΠ΅
Π°Π½ΡΡΠΎΠΏΠΎΠ»ΠΎΠ³ΠΈΡΠ΅, Π½Π° ΠΊΠΎΡΠΎΡ ΠΠ΄ΠΎΡΠ½ΠΎ Π·Π°ΡΠ½ΠΈΠ²Π° ΡΠ²ΠΎΡΡ ΠΊΡΠΈΡΠΈΠΊΡ Π‘ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΎΠ³. ΠΠ΅
ΡΠ΅Π³ΡΠ΅ΡΠΈΡΠ°ΡΡΡΠΈ Ρ Π½Π΅ΡΡΠ΄ΡΠΊΠΎ ΠΈ ΠΏΡΠΈΠΌΠΈΡΠΈΠ²Π½ΠΎ, ΠΌΡΠ·ΠΈΠΊΠ° Π‘ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΎΠ³ ΠΏΠΎΡΠ²ΡΡΡΡΠ΅, Ρ
ΠΈΡΡΠΎΡΠΈΡΡΠΊΠΈ Π°Π΄Π΅ΠΊΠ²Π°ΡΠ½ΠΈΠΌ ΠΌΠΎΠ΄Π΅ΡΠ½ΠΈΠΌ ΡΠ΅ΡΠΌΠΈΠ½ΠΈΠΌΠ°, ΠΊΠΎΠ½ΡΡΠΈΡΡΡΠΈΠ²Π½Ρ ΡΠ΅ΡΠ»Π΅ΠΊΡΠΈΠ²Π½ΠΎΡΡ
ΡΡΠ΄ΡΠΊΠΎΠ³ ΠΎΡΠ΅Π»ΠΎΡΠ²ΠΎΡΠ΅Π½ΠΎΠ³ ΡΡΠ°ΡΠ°, ΠΏΠΎΡΡΠ°ΡΡΡΠΈ ΡΠ°ΠΊΠΎ Π²ΠΈΡΠ΅ βΡΡΠ΄ΡΠΊΠ°β, ΡΡ. ΡΠΌΠΈΡΠ»Π΅Π½Π° ΠΈ
ΠΈΠ·ΡΠ°ΠΆΠ°ΡΠ½Π°, Π½Π΅Π³ΠΎ ΡΡΠΎ ΡΠ΅ ΠΠ΄ΠΎΡΠ½ΠΎ ΠΌΠΎΠ³Π°ΠΎ ΠΏΠΎΡΠΌΠΈΡΠΈ. ΠΡΠΈΠΌ ΡΠΎΠ³Π°, ΠΏΠ°ΠΆΡΠ° ΡΠ΅ ΠΏΠΎΡΠ²Π΅ΡΠ΅Π½Π°
ΠΈ Π½Π΅ΠΊΠΈΠΌ ΡΠ΅Π²ΠΎΠ»ΡΡΠΈΠΎΠ½Π°ΡΠ½ΠΈΠΌ ΠΌΡΠ·ΠΈΡΠΊΠΈΠΌ ΠΊΠ²Π°Π»ΠΈΡΠ΅ΡΠΈΠΌΠ° ΠΊΠΎΡΠΈ ΠΏΠΎΠ΄ΡΠΏΠΈΡΡ ΡΠΌΠ΅ΡΠ½ΠΈΡΠΊΡ
Π²ΡΠ΅Π΄Π½ΠΎΡΡ ΠΌΡΠ·ΠΈΠΊΠ΅ Π‘ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΎΠ³, ΠΊΠΎΡΡ ΡΠ΅ ΠΠ΄ΠΎΡΠ½ΠΎ ΡΠ°ΠΊΠΎΡΠ΅ ΠΎΡΠΏΠΎΡΠ°Π²Π°ΠΎ.Π£ΡΠ²Π°ΡΠ°ΡΡΡΠΈ ΠΌΠ°ΡΠΊΡΠΈΡΡΠΈΡΠΊΠΎ ΡΠ°Π·ΡΠΌΠ΅Π²Π°ΡΠ΅ ΡΡΠ΄ΡΠΊΠ΅ ΠΏΡΠΈΡΠΎΠ΄Π΅ ΠΊΠ°ΠΎ Π½Π΅ΡΠ΅Π³Π° ΡΡΠΎ ΡΠ΅
ΠΈΡΡΠΎΡΠΈΡΡΠΊΠΈ Π²Π°ΡΠΈΡΠ°Π±ΠΈΠ»Π½ΠΎ, ΠΠ΄ΠΎΡΠ½ΠΎ ΡΠΌΠ°ΡΡΠ° Π΄Π° Π‘ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΈ, ΠΎΠΏΠΎΠ²ΡΠ³Π°Π²Π°ΡΡΡΠΈ Ρ ΡΠ²ΠΎΡΠΎΡ
ΠΌΡΠ·ΠΈΡΠΈ ΠΌΠΎΠ΄Π΅ΡΠ½ΠΈ ΠΎΠ±Π»ΠΈΠΊ ΠΎΠ²Π΅ ΠΏΡΠΈΡΠΎΠ΄Π΅ Π½Π° ΠΈΠ΄Π΅ΠΎΠ»ΠΎΡΠΊΠΈ Π±ΡΠ΅ΠΌΠ΅Π½ΠΈΡ Π½Π°ΡΠΈΠ½, ΠΏΠΎΡΠ²ΡΡΡΡΠ΅
Π°ΡΠΏΠ΅ΠΊΡΠ΅ Π½Π΅ΡΡΠ΄ΡΠΊΠΎΡΡΠΈ ΠΈ Π²Π°ΡΠ²Π°ΡΠΈΠ·ΠΌΠ°. ΠΠΏΠ°ΠΊ, ΠΏΡΠ΅ΠΌΠ° ΡΠΈΠ»ΠΎΠ·ΠΎΡΡΠΊΠΎΡ Π°Π½ΡΡΠΎΠΏΠΎΠ»ΠΎΠ³ΠΈΡΠΈ
Π₯Π΅Π»ΠΌΡΡΠ° ΠΠ»Π΅ΡΠ½Π΅ΡΠ°, ΡΠ°ΠΌΠΎΡΠ²Π΅ΡΠ½ΠΎΡΡ ΠΈ ΡΠ°ΠΌΠΎΠΎΠΏΡΠ΅Π΄Π΅ΡΠ΅ΡΠ΅, Π½Π°Π²ΠΎΠ΄Π½ΠΎ Π°ΡΠΏΠ΅ΠΊΡΠΈ ΠΌΠΎΠ΄Π΅ΡΠ½Π΅
Ρ
ΡΠΌΠ°Π½ΠΎΡΡΠΈ, Ρ ΡΡΠ²Π°ΡΠΈ ΡΡ Π½Π΅Π²Π°ΡΠΈΡΠ°Π±ΠΈΠ»Π½ΠΈ Π°ΡΠΏΠ΅ΠΊΡΠΈ ΡΠ²Π°ΠΊΠ΅ ΡΡΠ΄ΡΠΊΠΎΡΡΠΈ. ΠΠ°ΠΎ ΡΠ°ΠΊΠ²ΠΈ,
ΠΎΠ½ΠΈ Π½Π΅ Π½Π΅ΡΡΠ°ΡΡ ΡΠ°ΠΊ ΠΈ Ρ ΡΠ»ΡΡΠ°ΡΡ βΠΏΡΠΈΠΌΠΈΡΠΈΠ²Π½ΠΎΠ³β ΠΈΠ»ΠΈ ΠΈΠ½ΡΠ°Π½ΡΠΈΠ»Π½ΠΎΠ³ ΠΏΠΎΠ½Π°ΡΠ°ΡΠ°,
Π½Π°ΡΠΎΡΠΈΡΠΎ ΠΊΠ°Π΄Π° ΡΠ΅ ΡΠ°ΠΊΠ²ΠΎ ΠΏΠΎΠ½Π°ΡΠ°ΡΠ΅ Π΄ΠΎΠ±ΡΠΎΠ²ΠΎΡΠ½ΠΎ ΠΈ ΡΠ΅ΡΠ»Π΅ΠΊΡΠΈΠ²Π½ΠΎ ΡΡΠ²ΠΎΡΠ΅Π½ΠΎ, ΠΊΠ°ΠΎ
Ρ ΡΠ»ΡΡΠ°ΡΡ ΠΌΡΠ·ΠΈΠΊΠ΅ Π‘ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΎΠ³. Π‘Π°ΠΌΠΎΡΠ²Π΅ΡΠ½ΠΎΡΡ ΠΈ ΡΠ°ΠΌΠΎΠΎΠΏΡΠ΅Π΄Π΅ΡΠ΅ΡΠ΅ ΠΎΠ²Π΄Π΅ ΡΠ΅
ΡΠ°Π·ΠΌΠ°ΡΡΠ°ΡΡ ΠΊΠ°ΠΎ Π΅ΡΠ΅Π½ΡΠΈΡΠ°Π»Π½Π΅ ΠΊΠ°ΡΠ°ΠΊΡΠ΅ΡΠΈΡΡΠΈΠΊΠ΅ ΡΠΏΠ΅ΡΠΈΡΠ°Π»Π½ΠΎΠ³, ΡΡΠ΄ΡΠΊΠΎΠ³ ΠΎΠ±Π»ΠΈΠΊΠ° ΠΆΠΈΠ²ΠΎΡΠ°
ΠΊΠΎΡΠΈ ΡΠ΅ ΠΊΠ°ΡΠ°ΠΊΡΠ΅ΡΠΈΡΠ΅ βΠ΅ΠΊΡΡΠ΅Π½ΡΡΠΈΡΠ½ΠΈΠΌ ΠΏΠΎΠ·ΠΈΡΠΈΠΎΠ½ΠΈΡΠ°ΡΠ΅ΠΌβ, ΡΠ΅ΡΠΌΠΈΠ½ΠΎΠΌ ΠΊΠΎΡΠΈ ΡΠ΅
ΠΊΠΎΡΠΈΡΡΠΈ ΠΊΠ°ΠΊΠΎ Π±ΠΈ ΡΠ΅ ΠΎΠ·Π½Π°ΡΠΈΠ»Π° ΡΡΡΡΠΊΡΡΡΠ°Π»Π½Π° Π΄ΠΈΡΡΠ°Π½ΡΠ° ΠΆΠΈΠ²ΠΎΠ³ Π±ΠΈΡΠ° Ρ ΠΎΠ΄Π½ΠΎΡΡ Π½Π°
ΡΠ΅Π±Π΅. Π‘ΡΡΡΠΊΡΡΡΠ°Π»Π½Π° Π΄ΠΈΡΡΠ°Π½ΡΠ° ΡΡΠ΄ΠΈ ΠΎΠ΄ ΡΠΈΡ
ΠΎΠ²ΠΈΡ
ΡΠ΅Π»Π° ΠΎΠΌΠΎΠ³ΡΡΠ°Π²Π° ΠΈΡΡΠΎΠ²ΡΠ΅ΠΌΠ΅Π½ΠΎ
ΠΏΡΠ°Π³ΠΌΠ°ΡΠΈΡΠ½Ρ ΠΈ Π΅ΡΡΠ΅ΡΡΠΊΡ ΠΊΠΎΠ½ΡΡΠΎΠ»Ρ ΡΠΈΡ
ΠΎΠ²ΠΈΡ
ΡΠ΅Π»Π° ΠΈ ΡΡΡΡΠΊΡΡΡΠ° ΡΠΈΡ
ΠΎΠ²Π΅ ΠΏΠ΅ΡΡΠ΅ΠΏΡΠΈΡΠ΅
Ρ ΠΏΠΎΠ³Π»Π΅Π΄Ρ ΠΌΠ°ΡΠ΅ΡΠΈΡΠ°Π»Π½Π΅ ΡΠΎΡΠΌΠ΅, Π΅ΠΊΡΠΏΡΠ΅ΡΠΈΡΠ΅ ΠΈ Π·Π½Π°ΡΠ΅ΡΠ°. Π’Π°ΠΊΠΎ ΡΠ΅ ΠΌΡΠ·ΠΈΠΊΠ° Π‘ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΎΠ³
ΡΠ²Π΅ΠΊ β Π²Π΅Ρ Π΅ΠΊΡΠΏΡΠ΅ΡΠΈΠ²Π½Π° ΠΈ ΡΠΌΠΈΡΠ»Π΅Π½Π°, ΠΈΠΌΠ° βΠ΄ΡΡΡβ ΠΈ βΠ΄ΡΡ
β, Π±Π΅Π· ΠΎΠ±Π·ΠΈΡΠ° Π½Π° ΠΈΠ½ΡΠ΅Π½ΡΠΈΡΠ΅
ΠΊΠΎΠΌΠΏΠΎΠ·ΠΈΡΠΎΡΠ° ΠΈΠ»ΠΈ Π±ΠΈΠ»ΠΎ ΠΊΠΎΠ³Π° Π΄ΡΡΠ³ΠΎΠ³. ΠΡΠΈΠΌ ΡΠΎΠ³Π°, ΡΠΏΡΠ°Π²ΠΎ ΡΠ΅ Ρ ΠΏΠ»Π΅ΡΠ½ΠΎΠΌ ΡΡΠ°Π²Ρ
β ΠΊΠΎΡΠΈ Π½ΠΈΡΠ΅ ΠΎΡΠΈΡΠ΅Π½ΡΠΈΡΠ°Π½ ΠΊΠ° ΡΠΈΡΡ Π½Π΅Π³ΠΎ ΠΈΠΌΠ° ΡΡΡΡΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΎ Π·Π½Π°ΡΠ΅ΡΠ΅ β Ρ
ΡΠΌΠ°Π½ΠΎΡΡ
ΠΏΠΎΠΊΠ°Π·ΡΡΠ΅ Ρ Π½Π°ΡΠ²Π΅ΡΠΎΠΌ ΡΠ°ΡΠ½ΠΎΡΠΎΠΌ. Π’ΠΎ ΡΠ΅ ΡΠΎΡ ΠΎΡΠΈΠ³Π»Π΅Π΄Π½ΠΈΡΠ΅ Ρ ΠΏΠ»Π΅ΡΠ½ΠΈΠΌ ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΎΠ²ΠΈΠΌΠ°
ΠΊΠ°ΠΎ ΠΎΠ½ΠΈΠΌ Ρ ΠΌΡΠ·ΠΈΡΠΈ Π‘ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΎΠ³, Π³Π΄Π΅ Π½Π΅ΠΏΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ»Π½ΠΎΡΡΠΈ ΠΈ Π²Π°ΡΠΈΡΠ°Π±ΠΈΠ»Π½ΠΎΡΡ ΠΌΠ΅ΡΡΠ°
ΠΈ Π°ΠΊΡΠ΅Π½ΡΠ° ΠΈΠ·ΠΈΡΠΊΡΡΡ Π½Π°ΡΠ²Π΅ΡΡ ΠΌΠΎΠ³ΡΡΡ ΠΊΠΎΠ½ΡΡΠΎΠ»Ρ Π½Π°Π΄ ΡΠ΅Π»ΠΎΠΌ ΠΊΠΎΡΠ΅ ΠΏΠ»Π΅ΡΠ΅. Π£ ΡΠ²Π°ΠΊΠΎΠΌ
ΡΠ»ΡΡΠ°ΡΡ, ΡΠΈΡΠΌΠΈΡΠΊΠ΅ Π½Π΅ΠΏΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ»Π½ΠΎΡΡΠΈ, ΠΏΡΠ΅ΠΏΠΎΠ·Π½Π°ΡΡΠΈΠ² ΠΈΠ΄Π΅Π½ΡΠΈΡΠ΅Ρ ΠΊΠΎΡΠΈ Π΄ΠΈΡΠΎΠ½Π°Π½ΡΠ½ΠΈ
Π°ΠΊΠΎΡΠ΄ΠΈ ΠΈ ΡΠ΅ΠΊΠ²Π΅Π½ΡΠ΅ ΡΠΈΡ
Π°ΠΊΠΎΡΠ°Π΄Π° ΠΏΠΎΡΡΠΈΠΆΡ ΠΊΡΠΎΠ· ΡΠ΅ΠΏΠ΅ΡΠΈΡΠΈΡΡ, ΡΠ»ΠΎΠ±ΠΎΠ΄Π½ΠΎ ΠΎΠ±Π»ΠΈΠΊΠΎΠ²Π°ΡΠ΅
ΡΠΎΡΠΌΠ΅ Ρ ΠΏΠΎΠ³Π»Π΅Π΄Ρ ΡΡΡΡΠΊΡΡΡΠ΅ ΠΊΠΎΡΠ΅ ΡΠ΅Π·ΡΠ»ΡΠΈΡΠ° ΠΈΠΌΠΏΡΠ»ΡΠΈΠΌΠ° ΠΈΠ³ΡΠ΅ ΡΠ΅Π½ΠΈΡ
Π΅Π»Π΅ΠΌΠ΅Π½Π°ΡΠ° ΠΈΠ·Π²Π°Π½ ΠΌΠΎΡΠΈΠ²ΡΠΊΠΎ-ΡΠ΅ΠΌΠ°ΡΡΠΊΠ΅ Π΅Π»Π°Π±ΠΎΡΠ°ΡΠΈΡΠ΅, ΡΠ°Π·Π²ΠΎΡΠ½ΠΈΡ
Π²Π°ΡΠΈΡΠ°ΡΠΈΡΠ° ΠΈΠ»ΠΈ ΡΠΎΡΠΌΠ°Π»Π½Π΅
ΡΠ΅Π»Π΅ΠΎΠ»ΠΎΠ³ΠΈΡΠ΅, ΠΎΡΠ²Π°ΡΠ°ΡΠ΅ Π½Π΅ΠΎΠ³ΡΠ°Π½ΠΈΡΠ΅Π½ΠΎΠ³ Ρ
ΠΎΡΠΈΠ·ΠΎΠ½ΡΠ° Π·Π²ΡΡΠ½ΠΈΡ
ΠΊΠΎΠΌΠ±ΠΈΠ½Π°ΡΠΈΡΠ° ΠΊΠΎΡΠ΅
Π΄Π°ΡΡ ΡΠ°ΠΊΡΠΎΡ Π΅ΡΡΠ΅ΡΡΠΊΠ΅ ΡΠ΅Π»Π΅Π²Π°Π½ΡΠ½ΠΎΡΡΠΈ Π½Π΅ ΡΠ°ΠΌΠΎ ΠΈΠ½ΡΠ΅ΡΠ²Π°Π»ΡΠΊΠΎΡ, Π½Π΅Π³ΠΎ ΠΈ ΡΠΈΠΌΠ±ΡΠ°Π»Π½ΠΎΡ
Π°ΡΡΠΈΠΊΡΠ»Π°ΡΠΈΡΠΈ Ρ
Π°ΡΠΌΠΎΠ½ΡΠΊΠΈΡ
ΠΊΠΎΠΌΠΏΠ»Π΅ΠΊΡΠ°, ΡΠ°ΠΌΠΎ ΡΡ Π½Π΅ΠΊΠΈ ΠΎΠ΄ Π½ΠΎΠ²ΠΈΡ
ΡΠΌΠ΅ΡΠ½ΠΈΡΠΊΠΈΡ
ΠΎΡΠΎΠ±ΠΈΠ½Π° ΠΊΠΎΡΠ΅ ΠΏΠΎΠ΄ΡΠΆΠ°Π²Π°ΡΡ ΡΠΌΠ΅ΡΠ½ΠΈΡΠΊΡ Π²ΡΠ΅Π΄Π½ΠΎΡΡ ΠΌΡΠ·ΠΈΠΊΠ΅ Π‘ΡΡΠ°Π²ΠΈΠ½ΡΠΊΠΎΠ³ ΠΈ ΡΡΠ²Π°ΡΡ ΡΠ΅ ΠΎΠ΄
Π½Π°ΠΏΠ°Π΄Π° ΠΏΡΠΈΡΡΡΠ°ΡΠ½Π΅ ΠΊΡΠΈΡΠΈΠΊΠ΅
Using time-varying evidence to test models of decision dynamics: bounded diffusion vs. the leaky competing accumulator model
When people make decisions, do they give equal weight to evidence arriving at different times? A recent study (Kiani et al., 2008) using brief motion pulses (superimposed on a random moving dot display) reported a primacy effect: pulses presented early in a motion observation period had a stronger impact than pulses presented later. This observation was interpreted as supporting the bounded diffusion (BD) model and ruling out models in which evidence accumulation is subject to leakage or decay of early-arriving information. We use motion pulses and other manipulations of the timing of the perceptual evidence in new experiments and simulations that support the leaky competing accumulator (LCA) model as an alternative to the BD model. While the LCA does include leakage, we show that it can exhibit primacy as a result of competition between alternatives (implemented via mutual inhibition), when the inhibition is strong relative to the leak. Our experiments replicate the primacy effect when participants must be prepared to respond quickly at the end of a motion observation period. With less time pressure, however, the primacy effect is much weaker. For 2 (out of 10) participants, a primacy bias observed in trials where the motion observation period is short becomes weaker or reverses (becoming a recency effect) as the observation period lengthens. Our simulation studies show that primacy is equally consistent with the LCA or with BD. The transition from primacy-to-recency can also be captured by the LCA but not by BD. Individual differences and relations between the LCA and other models are discussed
Dynamics of decision-making: from evidence accumulation to preference and belief
Decision-making is a dynamic process that begins with the accumulation of evidence and ends with the adjustment of belief. Each step is itself subject to a number of dynamic processes, such as planning, information search and evaluation. Furthermore, choice behavior reveals a number of challenging patterns, such as order effects and contextual preference reversal. Research in this field has converged toward a standard computational framework for the process of evidence integration and belief updating, based on sequential sampling models, which under some conditions are equivalent to normative Bayesian theory (Gold and Shadlen, 2007). A variety of models have been developed within the sequential sampling framework that can account for accuracy, response-time distributional data, and the speed-accuracy trade-off (Busemeyer and Townsend, 1993; Usher and Mcclelland, 2001; Brown and Heathcote, 2008; Ratcliff and McKoon, 2008). Yet there are differences between these models with regard to the mechanism of decision-termination, the optimality of the decision and the temporal weighting of the evidence. There is also a need to extend this framework to preference type of decisions (where the criteria are up to the judge) and to enrich it so as to include control processes (such as exploration/exploitation), information search, and adaptation to the environment, thereby allowing it to capture richer decision problems; for example, when alternatives are not pre-defined, or when the decision-maker is not just accumulating evidence but also adapting beliefs about the data-generating process.
This Research Topic presents new work that investigates the dynamical and mathematical properties of evidence integration and its neural mechanisms and extends this framework to more complex decisions, such as those that occur during risky choice, preference formation, and belief updating. We hope these articles will encourage researchers to explore the computational and normative aspects of the decision process and the observed deviations. We briefly review here the contributions in this collection, starting from simple perceptual decisions in which the information flow is externally controlled to more complex decisions, which allow the observer to control the information flow and other learning strategies, and following on with preference formation
Human optional stopping in a heteroscedastic world
When making decisions, animals must trade off the benefits of information harvesting against the opportunity cost of prolonged deliberation. Deciding when to stop accumulating information and commit to a choice is challenging in natural environments, where the reliability of decision-relevant information may itself vary unpredictably over time (variable variance or "heteroscedasticity"). We asked humans to perform a categorization task in which discrete, continuously valued samples (oriented gratings) arrived in series until the observer made a choice. Human behavior was best described by a model that adaptively weighted sensory signals by their inverse prediction error and integrated the resulting quantities with a linear urgency signal to a decision threshold. This model approximated the output of a Bayesian model that computed the full posterior probability of a correct response, and successfully predicted adaptive weighting of decision information in neural signals. Adaptive weighting of decision information may have evolved to promote optional stopping in heteroscedastic natural environments. (PsycInfo Database Record (c) 2021 APA, all rights reserved)
The influence of attention on value integration
People often have to make decisions based on many pieces of information. Previous work has found that people are able to integrate values presented in a Rapid Serial Visual Presentation (RSVP) stream to make informed judgements on the overall stream value (Tsetsos et al., 2012). It is also well known that attentional mechanisms influence how people process information. However, it is unknown how attentional factors impact value judgements of integrated material. The current study is the first of its kind to investigate whether value judgements are influenced by attentional processes when assimilating information. Experiments 1 to 3 examined whether the attentional salience of an item within an RSVP stream affected judgements of overall stream value. The results showed that the presence of an irrelevant high or low value salient item biased people to judge the stream as having a higher or lower overall mean value, respectively. Experiments 4 to 7 directly tested Tsetsos et al.βs (2012) theory examining whether extreme values in an RSVP stream become over-weighted, thereby capturing attention more than other values in the stream. The results showed that the presence of both a high (Experiments 4, 6 and 7) and a low (Experiment 5) value outlier captures attention leading to less accurate report of subsequent items in the stream. Taken together the results showed that valuations can be influenced by attentional processes, and can lead to less accurate subjective judgements
- β¦