104 research outputs found
Ancient science and technology of colour : an introduction
Introduction to the Proceedings of the mentioned conference, published in OA in Technai 12-13, 2022-2
Parmenides and Empedocles on Krasis and Knowledge
Making mental phenomena to depend on certain elements or organs of the body is famously recognized as a distinctive feature of physiologia both in the so-called âautobiographyâ of Socrates in the Phaedo and in a further âdoxographicâ passage in the dialogue, where Simmias develops the argument that the soul is like âa blending and an attunementâ of the bodily elements. While no earlier thinker is mentioned here, one can easily identify Parmenides and Empedocles as two of the main supporters of the notion that thought and perception depend on the various blendings of the physical constituents of the body. That they had such a view is indeed well known thanks to a few fragments, for whose discussion Aristotleâs and Theophrastusâ comments prove to be particularly helpful. What neither Plato nor Aristotle acknowledge, though, is that no such specific bearer of mental functions as psyche is needed in this kind of account. As a matter of fact, both Parmenides and Empedocles share with the epic and lyric tradition the idea of the precariousness of human knowledge, due to the constant exposure of human beings to change. Yet they âtranslateâ the topos of human existence and thought subjected to the divine into a vision where the physical krasis of the body (not by chance, a medical notion) is all that matters
La logique de lâeoikos et ses transformations : XĂ©nophane, ParmĂ©nide, Platon
Lâadjectif eoikos apparaĂźt dans trois passages cruciaux de la pensĂ©e grecque (XĂ©nophane, fr. B35 ; ParmĂ©nide, fr. B8, 60 ; Platon, TimĂ©e, 29b3-c3), caractĂ©risant une certaine « ressemblance » Ă la vĂ©ritĂ© qui se veut constitutive du discours du savant. En fait, le long de cet examen on dĂ©couvre que les trois usages du terme ne peuvent pas ĂȘtre disposĂ©s le long dâune ligne continue, vu la difficultĂ© de comprendre Ă quelle notion de vĂ©ritĂ©, sous quel point de vue, et avec quel degrĂ© dâĂ©vidence, ce discours se veut « ressemblant » selon lâoccasion. Dans le cas de ParmĂ©nide, cet aspect passe mĂȘme au second plan, puisquâon assiste Ă la prĂ©dominance dâune autre connotation qui accompagne le terme eoikos Ă partir de lâusage homĂ©rique, Ă savoir celle de la « convenance » Ă un contexte communicatif. Lâarticle cherche dans lâensemble Ă Ă©clairer les dĂ©placements que subit la logique de la similitude (et des procĂ©dĂ©s analogiques qui sây greffent) en passant par des cadres ontologiques et Ă©pistĂ©mologiques aussi diffĂ©rents que le sont ceux de XĂ©nophane, ParmĂ©nide et Platon.The adjective eoikos appears in three crucial passages of Greek thought (Xenophanes, fr. B35; Parmenides, fr. B8, 60; Plato, Timaeus, 29b3âc3), in all of them expressing the notion of âresemblanceâ to the truth that is considered to be fundamental to the scientific discourse. In fact, this discussion shows that the three uses of the term cannot be arranged along a continuous line, owing to the difficulty in discerning what notion of truth, in what respect, and to what degree of clarity, this discourse should be âlikeâ from time to time. In the case of Parmenides, this aspect seems even to be of secondary importance, as in the term prevails another connotation, which accompanies eoikos from Homer onwards, namely, that of âconvenienceâ of a speech to a communicative context. The article seeks to enlighten the complicate course of the logic of similarity (and of the analogical procedures engaging with it) through such diverse ontological and epistemological frameworks as are those of Xenophanes, Parmenides, and the late Plato
Christopher Moore, Calling Philosophers Names . On the Origin of a Discipline
Cet ouvrage vigoureux, fruit dâune longue recherche que Christopher Moore a menĂ©e au cours des dix derniĂšres annĂ©es, propose une perspective nouvelle et stimulante sur les origines de la philosophie grecque. Plus prĂ©cisĂ©ment, comme lâexplique Moore dans le premier chapitre introductif (p. 1-33), il ne sâest pas fixĂ© pour objectif de reconstituer (la niĂšme fois) le dĂ©roulement des doctrines des penseurs grecs Ă partir de ThalĂšs, mais dâenquĂȘter sur les significations prises par le terme philos..
Maria Michela Sassi: A lĂłgica do eoikĂłs e suas transformaçÔes: XenĂłfanes, ParmĂȘnides, PlatĂŁo
Translation by Luiz OtĂĄvio de Figueiredo Mantovanelli of MARIA MICHELA SASSI\u27s paper:La Logique de l\u27Eoikos et ses transformations: XĂ©nophane, ParmĂ©nide, Platonoriginaly published in Philosophie Antique, n.13 (2013), 13-35Abstract:The adjective eoikĂłs appears in three crucial passages of Greek thought (Xenophanes, fr. B35; Parmenides, fr. B8, 60; Plato, Timaeus, 29b3-c3), in all of them expressing the notion of ressemblance to the truth that is considered to be fundamental to the scientific discourse. In fact, this discussion shows that the three uses of the term cannot be arranged along a continuous line, owing to the difficulty in discerning what notion of truth, in what respect, and to what degree of clarity, this discourse should be âlikeâ from time to time. In the case of Parmenides, this aspect seems even to be of secondary importance, as in the term prevails another connotation, wich accompanies eoikos from Homer onwards, namely, that of âconvenienceâ of a speech to a communicative context. The article seeks to enlighten the complicate course of the logic of similarity (and of the analogical procedures engaging with it) through such diverse ontological and epistemological frameworks as are those of Xenophanes, Parmenides and the Late Plato.Traduction en portugais par Luiz OtĂĄvio de Figueiredo Mantovanelli de l\u27 article de MARIA MICHELA SASSI:La Logique de l\u27Eoikos et ses transformations: XĂ©nophane, ParmĂ©nide, PlatonpubliĂ© originellement Ă Philosophie Antique, n.13 (2013), 13-35 Tradução por Luiz OtĂĄvio de Figueiredo Mantovanelli e RevisĂŁo de Cristiane A. de Azevedo do artigo de MARIA MICHELA SASSI:La Logique de l\u27Eoikos et ses transformations: XĂ©nophane, ParmĂ©nide, Platonpublicado originalmente em Philosophie Antique, n.13 (2013), 13-35Resumo: O adjetivo eoikĂłs aparece em trĂȘs passagens cruciais do pensamento grego (XenĂłfanes, fr. B35; ParmĂȘnides, fr. B8.60; PlatĂŁo. Timeu, 29b3-c3), caracterizando uma certa âsemelhançaâ com a verdade que se pretende constitutiva do discurso do sĂĄbio. De fato, ao longo da presente investigação, poderemos constatar que os trĂȘs empregos do termo nĂŁo podem ser dispostos numa linha contĂnua, devido Ă dificuldade de discernir a qual noção de verdade, sob qual ponto de vista, e com qual grau de evidĂȘncia, o discurso se pretende âsemelhanteâ de acordo com o contexto. No caso de ParmĂȘnides, tal aspecto passa em segundo plano, jĂĄ que hĂĄ lĂĄ a predominĂąncia de uma outra conotação que acompanha o termo eoikĂłs a partir do emprego homĂ©rico, a saber, o da âconveniĂȘnciaâ a um contexto comunicativo. O artigo procura no seu conjunto por em evidĂȘncia os deslocamentos sofridos pela lĂłgica da similitude (e os procedimentos analĂłgicos que lĂĄ se inserem) percorrendo quadros ontolĂłgicos e epistemolĂłgicos tĂŁo diferentes quanto os de XenĂłfanes, ParmĂȘnides e PlatĂŁo
Ultralight vector dark matter search using data from the KAGRA O3GK run
Among the various candidates for dark matter (DM), ultralight vector DM can be probed by laser interferometric gravitational wave detectors through the measurement of oscillating length changes in the arm cavities. In this context, KAGRA has a unique feature due to differing compositions of its mirrors, enhancing the signal of vector DM in the length change in the auxiliary channels. Here we present the result of a search for U(1)BâL gauge boson DM using the KAGRA data from auxiliary length channels during the first joint observation run together with GEO600. By applying our search pipeline, which takes into account the stochastic nature of ultralight DM, upper bounds on the coupling strength between the U(1)BâL gauge boson and ordinary matter are obtained for a range of DM masses. While our constraints are less stringent than those derived from previous experiments, this study demonstrates the applicability of our method to the lower-mass vector DM search, which is made difficult in this measurement by the short observation time compared to the auto-correlation time scale of DM
- âŠ