26 research outputs found
The dynamics of the contemporary supreme constitution viewed in light of pre- and early modern views of supremacy of the law and popular sovereignty
Constitutional supremacy – the contemporary refined form of the supremacy of the law –
is the foundation upon which present supreme constitutions such as that of the United
States of America and South Africa are based. Nevertheless, we find the opposite
principle, namely that of popular sovereignty also featuring prominently in these
constitutions. According to the doctrine underpinning the supreme constitution, the
tension between the two is decisively resolved in favour of the supremacy of the law (and
the constitution). However, there is a growing critical literature which questions whether
the supremacy principle is actually predominant. It is argued, for example, that the most
important changes to supreme constitutions result from dominant forces within the
populus, beyond the amendment provisions of these constitutions. This literature underscores
the need to revisit the relationship between legal supremacy and popular
sovereignty. This article enquires into this question, more specifically with reference to
the possible insights that might be gained from certain trends in the pre-modern and early
modern thinking regarding the relationship between these two principles. The inquiry
shows that the conceptions of legal supremacy and popular sovereignty were unified into
one single harmonious constitutional theory. This article describes and explains this
erstwhile union. It is concluded that popular sovereignty in the form of communal custom,
or more correctly, the customs and practices of the dominant forces within the populus,
were the active driving force of pre-modern constitutionalism. This is informative for
present constitutional theory as it explains why the dominant forces within the populus so
decisively determine the fate of the supreme constitution.http://www.lexisnexis.co.zaam2016Public La
Constitutional perspectives on the judgments of the Labour Appeal Court and the Supreme Court of Appeal in Solidarity (acting on behalf of Barnard) v South African Police Services
Save for a possible appeal to the Constitutional Court, the unanimous judgment of the Supreme Court of Appeal (SCA) in Solidarity (acting on behalf of Barnard) v South African Police Services (Vereniging van Regslui vir Afrikaans amicus curiae) (Case number 165/2013 delivered on 28 November 2013) has brought to a close a legal battle of more than eight years between Captain Renate Barnard and the South African Police Services (SAPS) on Barnard's promotion to the rank of superintendent. The saga surrounding Barnard's promotion began in 2005. It went through the internal grievance procedure, the Commission for Conciliation, Mediation and Arbitration (CCMA), the Labour Court (LC) and then the Labour Appeal Court (LAC). Barnard was successful in the LC (Solidarity abo Barnard v SAPS 2010 (10) BCLR 1094 (LC)) but on appeal by the SAPS to the LAC in South African Police Services v Solidarity abo Barnard (2013 (3) BCLR 320 (LAC)) she was unsuccessful. The judgment of the SCA was on appeal from a ruling of the LAC.http://www.dejure.up.ac.za/am201
Anderkant verstaatlikte konstitusionalisme
Openbare regeringsgesag, wat binne ʼn konstitusionele orde uitgeoefen word, is ʼn deurlopende
essensie van die politiek en die konstitusionele reg. Die huidige territoriale staat, waarin ons
ons tans bevind, is bloot een van verskeie verskyningsvorme waarbinne openbare gesag
uitgeoefen word.1 Dit is nie permanent nie. Ingelui deur Engeland en Frankryk het die territoriale
staat ʼn duidelik aanduibare ontstaan gedurende die sestiende en sewentiende eeue beleef en
as historiese verskynsel is dit onvermydelik bestem om ook tot ’n einde te kom. Diegene wat
met die territoriale staat omgaan asof dit bykans a-histories en tydloos is, kan hulself gerus
daaraan herinner dat selfs Thomas Hobbes wat die magtige Leviatan in goddelike terme beskryf
het, darem begryp het dat dié god oplaas ʼn tydelike – sterflike – god is.http://www.journals.co.za/content/journal/akgeeshttp://www.scielo.org.za/scielo.php?script=sci_serial&pid=0041-4751&lng=enam2017Public La
Deliberating the rule of law and constitutional supremacy from the perspective of the factual dimension of law
This discussion critiques the generally accepted doctrine of the rule of law and constitutional supremacy prevalent in contemporary constitutional states, including the doctrine as conceived in terms of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa.
The critique proceeds from the view that law, more specifically positive law is essentially two-dimensional. On the one hand there is the dimension of justice; that is, law's justice, moral or critical dimension (and requisite). On the other hand there is law's factual dimension (and requisite). Both of these dimensions are essential for an individual norm to qualify as a norm of positive law. By the same token, on a comprehensive basis both dimensions are also essential requisites for a system of law to be in place. A clear understanding of the two-dimensionality of law provides the basis for the critique presented in the present discussion, which is focussed upon the factual dimension of law. It will be pointed out that the leading doctrine on the rule of law and constitutional supremacy prevalent in contemporary constitutional states is premised on a failure to account for the factual dimension; and that the doctrine in consequence obscures a clear insight into the factual dimension of law, and therefore obscures a clear understanding of the nature and content of (positive) law, including the constitution.http://www.nwu.ac.za/p-per/index.htmlhb201
To what extent should the convention of cabinet secrecy still be recognised in South African constitutional law?
This note deals with the question whether, under the present-day South
African constitutional law, members of the public are entitled to any
information held by cabinet (the national executive). This question is
considered with specific reference to the law of comparative
jurisdictions. Two competing principles must be considered: on the one
hand, the constitutional right of access to information held by the state
(cabinet information in the present case) and, on the other hand, the
convention of cabinet secrecy. The latter originated in English
constitutional law, which might be argued to have been inherited by
South Africa.http://www.dejure.up.ac.za/hb2016Public La
Language deterioration with specific reference to the ideologies and practices of statism
It is argued in this article that the ideology of statism has been playing a major part in the accelerated
rate of the deterioration and extinction of languages. Beginning with some general observations
on the reason for language deterioration and extinction the emphasis subsequently shifts to the
ideology of statism as a major factor determining the fate of minority languages. Statism refers to
the territorial state with its single largely industrialised economy spanning the territory of the whole state and organised in terms of its own distinctive statist ideology, that reinforces and justifies
a state-wide homogeneous nation and the monolingualism of a single dominant (state) language
to the detriment of all other (minority) languages. The statist ideology might be slanting to the left,
the right or the liberal centre but it always acts in defence and in support of the homogenising
monolingual territorial state. The statist ideology and the dictates of the industrialised economy
are interdependent and mutually reinforcing, both working towards the homogenisations and
monolingualism of the territorial state. Statism harks back to the consolidation of the modern
territorial state in England and France in the sixteenth century, soon followed by the other European
territorial states and thereafter in the rest of the world. The advent of the first territorial states was
accompanied with the emergence of large scale industrial homogenising economies in the place
of the erstwhile localised agrarian economies. In discussing the homogenising and particularly
monolingual consequences of the state-wide industrial economy the elucidating insights of Ernst
Gellner are discussed in some detail. The ideology of statism comes in a variety of mutations
spanning the entire ideological spectrum from left to right, however consistently having the same
homogenising goal and effect also as far as language is concerned. All these ideologies, regardless
of how divergent they are, are in the final analysis species of the same larger genus, namely the
ideology of statism. In dealing with these species the French position with a more specific emphasis
on the Jacobin and nationalist policies in relation to languages since the French Revolution is first
dealt with. This is followed by an assessment of the position of language in terms of the right-wing nationalist approach in Spain which reached its zenith under the dictatorship of Franco. Thereafter
the approach to language in Britain is discussed with reference to the impact of Anglicisation upon
the Celtic languages of the British Isles. This approach was at least in part founded upon and
received further momentum in the convictions articulated by some of the foremost liberal political
theorists such as John Stuart Mill. The American approach – seemingly the purist liberal one – is
then discussed with reference to the impact of monoculturalism on the minority languages of the
United States. Subesequently, the focus shifts to the other extreme of the ideological spectrum when
the Leftist approach to language with reference to Marx and Engels is assessed. The discussion
reveals that the approaches in relation to languages were, if not in theoretical design, then most
certainly in purpose and effect essentially the same in terms of all these ideological positions
irrespective of the ideological orientations of their authors. What all of these approaches share
– whether pursued from the left, right or the liberal centre – is the statist ideology which serves as
the common foundation for all of them. The conclusion drawn from this is that smaller languages,
that is, languages with minoritised linguistic communities stand in the way of an encompassing
collection of modern ideologies that share the common ideological matrix of statism. Smaller
languages and their communities are therefore imperilled by the broadly encompassing ideology
of statism and not merely by an ideological assault forthcoming from a right-wing, left-wing or
similarly distinctive ideology that occupies a specific position on the ideological spectrum. It is
this encompassing challenge of statism that smaller linguistic communities need to overcome.In hierdie artikel word aangevoer dat verstaatliking in die moderne tydperk die belangrikste oorsaak
vir die verdwyning van tale is. Verstaatliking verwys eerstens na die omvangryke territoriale staat,
waarin ’n bepaalde dominante elite neig om sy eie karakter en identiteit aan die staat as sodanig
toe te dig en van alle ander gemeenskappe (in ’n nie-oorheersende posisie) vereis om hulself in
hierdie staatlike identiteit op te los. Tweedens verwys dit na die moderne industriële ekonomie,
wat ’n sterk homogeniserende krag is wat eentaligheid in die hand werk. Derdens verwys dit na
die ideologie van verstaatliking wat regverdiging vir die homogeniserende staat verskaf. Opvallend
van die ideologie van verstaatliking is dat dit omvattend is en in verskeie verskyningsvorme oral
oor die spektrum van die ideologiese skaal manifesteer. Dit sluit regse nasionalisme, Jakobinisme,
tendense van die liberale politiek asook die linkse sosialisme in. In weerwil van die oënskynlik
beduidende verskille tussen hierdie ideologieë en bypassende praktyke, wat oor die afgelope eeue
van die belangrikste kragte in die politiek was, is hulle veranker in ’n enkele gemeenskaplike
ideologiese matriks, naamlik dié van verstaatliking. Ofskoon daar ’n groeiende tendens in sowel
die politieke denke as staatsregtelike praktyk is om minderheidsgemeenskappe
met hulle eiesoortige
kulturele bates (soos hulle tale) op ’n demokratiese wyse te akkommodeer, het die ideologie van
verstaatliking nog lank nie sy houvas verloor nie en hou dit steeds ’n enorme bedreiging vir die
voortbestaan van minderheidstale tale en minderheidsgemeenskappe
in.http://www.journals.co.za/ej/ejour_akgees.htmlam201
Decided correctly within the parameters of essentially irrelevant law
In Lourens v Speaker of the National Assembly 2015 1 SA 618 (EqC) the court held that the practice not to publish all national legislation in all eleven official languages is not constitutionally offensive, more specifically that it does not constitute unfair discrimination incompatible with section 9 of the Constitution and the relevant provisions of the Promotion of Equality and Prevention of Unfair Discrimination Act 4 of 2000. The court accepted in favour of the applicant that the practice not to publish all legislation in all official languages constitutes discrimination on the basis of language, but found the evidence tendered on behalf of the first respondent convincing enough to rebut the presumption of unfairness (of the discrimination) and therefore it is not unconstitutional.http://www.litnet.co.za/Category/akademies/litnet-akademieshttp://reference.sabinet.co.za/sa_epublication/litnet?am201
Heerskappy van die reg teenoor desisionisme in die Suid-Afrikaanse grondwetlike diskoers
Die heerskappy van die reg (rule of law) is een van die grondliggende
waardes van die Suid-Afrikaanse grondwetlike orde. Saam met ’n aantal
ander waardes wat in artikel 1 van die Grondwet van die Republiek van Suid-
Afrika van 1996 vervat is, omskryf dit die eenstemmige waardekompleks
waarop die huidige grondwetlike orde berus. Hierdie bydrae ontleed onlangse
gebeure in die Suid-Afrikaanse grondwetlike diskoers, meer bepaald: (1) die
omstredenheid rondom die Regterlike Dienskommissie se hantering van die
klagtes van die regters van die Konstitusionele Hof teen regterpresident John
Hlophe en (2) die president se verlenging van die ampstermyn van die vorige
hoofregter kragtens ’n ongrondwetlike wetsbepaling. Daar word geargumenteer
dat die omstredenheid te wyte is aan twee onversoenbare
denkbeelde oor die heerskappy van die reg. Die een is die klassieke konsep
van oppergesag van die reg, wat op die beginsel van legaliteit gegrond is, en
die ander, hier desisionisme genoem, is gegrond op ’n “norm” van die
“beste” besluit in die omstandighede. Hierdie diepliggende verskil spruit
voort uit twee uiteenlopende (regs)kulture. Die een het ’n skriftuurlike
grondslag en is geanker in ’n soewereine corpus van reg teenoor die ander
een wat mondeling en teenswoordig-gesentreerd is en wat nie met die idee
van ’n soewereine corpus van reg soos dit eeue lank in veral die Westerse
regskultuur bestaan, bekend is nie.http://www.dejure.up.ac.za/am2013ai201
An assessment of the forces impacting on the meaning and outcome of the discretionary official language clause of the South African Constitution
In ’n bydrae in SA Publiekreg/SA Public Law (ter perse) is uiteengesit dat die taalbepalings,
hierna “die taalklousule” genoem, vervat in artikel 6 van die Suid-Afrikaanse grondwet ’n
sterk diskresionĂŞre karakter het. Die gesaghebbende interpreterende gemeenskap van hierdie
bepaling, wat hoofsaaklik kom vanuit die huidige toonaangewende Afronasionalistiese
stroming in Suid-Afrika, het derhalwe aansienlike beweegruimte om by wyse van hulle
besondere vertolking van hierdie klousule konkrete inhoud daaraan te verleen. Teen hierdie
agtergrond is dit van groot belang om te bepaal wat die sosiopolitieke kragte is wat in daardie
geledere werksaam is en wat gevolglik die konkrete inhoud van die bepaling via die
interpretasie daarvan bepaal. In hierdie ondersoek word aangetoon dat dieselfde kragte wat in
Suid-Afrika werksaam is, eweneens elders in Afrika aan die werk is. Die belangrikste van
hierdie kragte word vervolgens geĂŻdentifiseer en ontleed. Daar word in die besonder op vier
hiervan gefokus: die kunsmatigheid van die staat in Afrika; die aard van politieke bewussyn
in Afrika in samehang met die aard van Afrika-nasionalismes; die populĂŞre oortuiging dat
Engels (en die ander koloniale tale), anders as die inheemse tale, die weg baan om
ekonomiese en sosiale aspirasies te verwesenlik, en gevolglik ook as voertaal in die onderwys
verkies word; en laastens, dat die Afrikatale distansiërend met premoderniteit verbind word
teenoor Engels (en die ander koloniale tale) wat vereenselwigend met modernisering en
vooruitgang verbind word. Al vier hierdie kragte werk sterk ten gunste van Engels en
verengelsing, en teen die Afrikatale. Indien die Suid-Afrikaanse grondwet oor ’n taalklousule
beskik het wat in besonderhede uiteengesit het op welke wyse die inheemse tale hanteer en
bevorder moet word, kon dit ’n belangrike rol gespeel het om hierdie tale te ondersteun en
verengelsing teen te werk. Die diskresionĂŞre taalklousule het egter juis die teenoorgestelde
uitwerking deur as’t ware die werking van hierdie kragte aan te help in plaas daarvan om dit
te verswak.Section 6 of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa (the official language clause)
provides for eleven official languages. It then proceeds to create what on a proper analysis
amounts to a broad discretion for organs of state in relation to the actual treatment of the
official languages. (This aspect is fully explored in an article “The discretionary nature of the
official language clause”, SA Public Law / Publiekreg 2011, forthcoming). The way in which
this discretion has been exercised (in conjunction with some other factors) has decisively
steered South Africa in the direction of an official English monolingual state in all domains
of official language use.
The question which this article seeks to answer is why this has been happening. To answer
the question one needs to identify the forces that are causing organs of state to exercise their
discretion in this monolingual English fashion. The discretionary official language clause has
created space for these forces to determine the actual content of the official language
dispensation in South Africa. The same forces have also exerted a similar influence elsewhere
in African continent. The foremost of these forces are identified and assessed.http://www.litnet.co.za/cgi-bin/giga.cgi?cmd=cause_dir_news&cat=201&cause_id=127
Toepaslikheid en ontoepaslikheid van ubuntu in die staatsreg – intergemeenskapsbetrekkinge teenoor openbare ampsbekleding
In hierdie artikel word aangevoer dat ubuntu in bepaalde kontekste in die
staatsreg van besondere waarde kan wees, maar dat die toepaslikheid
daarvan op ander gebiede onder verdenking is. Wat die toepaslikheid
daarvan betref, word geredeneer dat daar ’n korpus van reg, genaamd die
reg van inter-gemeenskapsbetrekkinge aan die ontwikkel is. Die grondslag
hiervan is in die wesensaard van die staat self. Op die keper beskou is die
staat die beliggaming van, en waarborg vir die openbare vrede (of behoort
dit ten minste so te wees). Die openbare vrede is op sy beurt afhanklik van
die instandhouding van gesonde betrekkinge tussen gemeenskappe, by
gebreke waarvan die veiligheid van die gemeenskappe in die gedrang kom
en die stabiliteit, en trouens die voortbestaan van die staat self, in die
gedrang kom. In die bespreking word met verwysing na die beskouing in
Suid-Afrikaanse regspraak oor ubuntu aangevoer dat ubuntu saam met die
verbod op haatspraak en dergelike verbiedinge wat die openbare vrede
kan ontwrig, sowel as die internasionale reg rakende volksmoord en
verwante internasionale misdade, die ontluikende reg van intergemeenskapsbetrekkinge,
beliggaam. Daarenteen kan ubuntu egter
treffend ontoepaslik wees naamlik op die gebied van openbare
ampsbekleding. Die kernvraag by openbare ampsbekleding is of die
ampsbekleër vir die openbare amp waarin sy/haar aangestel is, geskik is
en die pligte wat met die amp vereenselwig word, soos dit in die
toepaslike reg beskryf word, getrou (kan) uitvoer. Openbare
ampsbekleding hang juis nie primĂŞr van die persoonlike verhoudings van
die ampsbekleër met die publiek of met die hoofde of ondersgeskiktes van
die ampsbekleër af nie. Inteendeel, warm verhoudings kan juis
verkeerdelik voortspruit uit oorwegings wat allermins met die betrokke
amp vereenselwigbaar is. Dit kan voorkom omdat die kunsmatige
identiteit van openbare ampsbekleding met vermeende ubuntugeĂŻnspireerde
knusse betrekkinge wat niks met die nakoming van
openbare ampspligte te doen het nie, verwar word. Om hierdie rede is die
aanwending van ubuntu-geĂŻnspireerde goeie verhoudings in die konteks
van openbare ampsbekding bevraagtekenbaar.The value of ubuntu, among other things encapsulating the notions of
humaneness, human dignity, reconciliation, group solidarity,
compassion, the establishment and the maintenance of warm relations
and restorative justice is autochthonous to South African law, more in particular South African constitutional law. Lately it has come to play an
increasingly important part in South African constitutional jurisprudence.
It is not possible to measure exactly how prominent the place is that
ubuntu occupies in the public order and in the public service. However,
judging by the Constitutional Court, who observed that the spirit of
ubuntu is part of the deep cultural heritage of the majority of the
population,1 ubuntu might be far more important than one might
generally tend to assume. This article assesses the relevance or otherwise
of ubuntu in constitutional law. The discussion proceeds from the
jurisprudence of the Constitutional Court on ubuntu, thus beginning in
section 2 with an overview of the judicial pronouncements on ubuntu.
This discussion casts light on the definition and the field of application of
ubuntu as viewed by the courts. There is a corpus of South African
academic literature on ubuntu.2 In this corpus ubuntu is generally very
favourably viewed. However, there is also stinging critique against
ubuntu as for example in the thoroughly researched article by Ilze Keevy,
who argues that ubuntu is fundamentally at odds with the values of
equality and tolerance as endorsed by the South African constitution.3
Moreover, even those who generally praised ubuntu as a lofty ethicallegal
value complex, encounter serious difficulties in their attempts to
offer a workable core-definition of ubuntu.4 Moreover, some attempts to
define ubuntu were to my mind so airy-fairy that they fail to
communicate anything of value about ubuntu.5 For that reason, but for a
few exceptions such as the discussion by Bilchitz, the academic
commentary is mainly left aside in this article. The focus instead is on
ubuntu as assessed by the courts. In the next two sections of the article
the rightful place that ubuntu should occupy in constitutional law is
considered. Hence, if there is a place for ubuntu, as the affirming dicta of
the courts clearly suggest, the question is how to delineate the boundaries of its applicability, and how to clarify where ubuntu should
have a place and a role and where not.
It is argued in section 3, and this leads to the first conclusion, that
ubuntu could be relevant and even of crucial importance in the sphere of
inter-communal relations and for the maintenance of inter-communal
peace, which is an essential condition for the very existence and survival
of the state. In this context ubuntu may be playing an important part in
what is here termed (an emerging) law of inter-communal relations,
which is in fact a core issue of constitutional law and for the well-being
of the state. However, in section 4 it is argued that there is a field of
constitutional law where it would be inappropriate to allow ubuntu to play
any part. This is in the context of certain aspects of public office-bearing,
which is an essential aspect of constitutional law and on which the
existence and well-being of the state depends. To allow ubuntu to play
any part in this context could arguably be to the detriment of the state.http://www.dejure.up.ac.za/hb201