29,281 research outputs found
Equality and information
Traditional outcome-orientated egalitarian principles require access
to information about the size of individual holdings. Recent egalitarian political theory has sought to accommodate considerations of responsibility. Such a move may seem problematic, in that a new informational burden is thereby introduced, with no apparent decrease in the existing burden. This article uses a simple model with simulated data to examine the extent to which outcome egalitarianism and responsibility-sensitive egalitarianism (âluck egalitarianismâ) can be accurately applied where information is incomplete or erroneous. It is found that, while outcome egalitarianism tends to be more accurately applied, its advantage is not overwhelming, and in many prima facie plausible circumstances luck egalitarianism would be more accurately applied. This suggests that luck egalitarianism cannot be rejected as utopian. Furthermore, while some argue that, in practice, luck egalitarianism is best realized indirectly, by securing equality of outcome, our evidence suggests that a luck egalitarian rule of regulation offers a far more accurate implementation of the luck egalitarian ideal than does an outcome egalitarian rule of regulation
Inequality, avoidability, and healthcare
This review article of Shlomi Segall's Health, Luck, and Justice (Princeton University Press, 2010) addresses three issues: first, Segallâs claim that luck egalitarianism, properly construed, does not object to brute luck equality; second, Segallâs claim that brute luck is properly construed as the outcome of actions that it would have been unreasonable to expect the agent to avoid; and third, Segallâs account of healthcare and criticism of rival views. On the first two issues, a more conventional form of luck egalitarianism â that is, one which objects to brute luck even if it creates equality, and which construes brute luck as the inverse of agent responsibility â is defended. On the third issue, strengths and weaknesses in Segallâs criticism of Rawlsian, democratic egalitarian, and all-luck egalitarian approaches to healthcare, and in his own luck egalitarian approach, are identified
The injustice of discrimination
Discrimination might be considered unjust on account of the comparative disadvantage it imposes, the absolute disadvantage it imposes, the disrespect it shows, or the prejudice it shows. This article argues that each of these accounts overlooks some cases of unjust discrimination. In response to this state of affairs we might combine two or more of these accounts. A promising approach combines the comparative disadvantage and absolute disadvantage accounts
What is grandfathering?
Emissions grandfathering maintains that prior emissions increase future emission entitlements. The view forms a large part of actual emission control frameworks, but is routinely dismissed by political theorists and applied philosophers as evidently unjust. A sympathetic theoretical reconsideration of grandfathering suggests that the most plausible version is moderate, allowing that other considerations should influence emission entitlements, and be justified on instrumental grounds. The most promising instrumental justification defends moderate grandfathering on the basis that one extra unit of emission entitlements from a baseline of zero emissions increases welfare to a greater extent where it is assigned to a high emitter than where it is assigned to a low emitter. Moderate grandfathering can be combined with basic needs and ability to pay considerations to provide an attractive approach to allocating emission entitlements
A pluralistic approach to global poverty
A large proportion of humankind today lives in avoidable poverty. This article examines whether affluent individuals and governments have moral duties to change this situation. It is maintained that an alternative to the familiar accounts of transdomestic distributive justice and personal ethics put forward by writers such as Peter Singer, John Rawls, and Thomas Pogge is required, since each of these accounts fails to reflect the full range of relevant considerations. A better account would give some weight to overall utility, the condition of the worst off, and individual responsibility. This approach provides robust support to global poverty alleviation
Benefiting from injustice and brute luck
Many political philosophers maintain that beneficiaries of injustice are under special obligations to assist victims of injustice. However, the examples favored by those who endorse this view equally support an alternative luck egalitarian view, which holds that special obligations should be assigned to those with good brute luck. From this perspective the distinguishing features of the benefiting view are (1) its silence on the question of whether to allocate special obligations to assist the brute luck worse off to those who are well off as a matter of brute luck but not as a result of injustice, and (2) its silence on the question of whether to allocate assistance to those who are badly off as a matter of brute luck but not as a result of injustice. In this new light, the benefiting view is harder to justify
Distributive luck
This article explores the Rawlsian goal of ensuring that distributions
are not influenced by the morally arbitrary. It does so by bringing discussions
of distributive justice into contact with the debate over
moral luck initiated by Williams and Nagel. Rawlsâ own justice as
fairness appears to be incompatible with the arbitrariness commitment,
as it creates some equalities arbitrarily. A major rival,
Dworkinâs version of brute luck egalitarianism, aims to be continuous
with ordinary ethics, and so is (a) sensitive to non-philosophical beliefs
about free will and responsibility, and (b) allows inequalities to
arise on the basis of option luck. But Dworkin does not present convincing
reasons in support of continuity, and there are compelling
moral reasons for justice to be sensitive to the best philosophical account
of free will and responsibility, as is proposed by the revised
brute luck egalitarianism of Arneson and Cohen. While Dworkinian
brute luck egalitarianism admits three sorts of morally arbitrary disadvantaging
which correspond to three forms of moral luck (constitutive,
circumstantial, and option luck), revised brute luck egalitarianism
does not disadvantage on the basis of constitutive or circumstantial
luck. But it is not as sensitive to responsibility as it needs to be to
fully extinguish the influence of the morally arbitrary, for persons under
it may exercise their responsibility equivalently yet end up with
different outcomes on account of option luck. It is concluded that
egalitarians should deny the existence of distributive luck, which is
luck in the levels of advantage that individuals are du
Egalitarian justice and valuational judgment
Contemporary discussions of egalitarian justice have often focused on the issue of expensive taste. G.A. Cohen has recently abandoned the view that all chosen disadvantages are non-compensable, now maintaining that chosen expensive judgmental tastesâthose endorsed by valuational judgmentâare compensable as it is unreasonable to expect persons not to develop them. But chosen expensive brute tasteâthe main type of non-compensable expensive taste on the new schemeâcannot be described in such a way that there is a normative difference between it and chosen expensive judgmental taste. As there are related problems with denying compensation for the other kind of expensive taste that might remain non-compensable, Cohen's position on taste appears to be either implausible or virtually indistinguishable from that of equality of welfare. However, compensation for valuational judgment-based expensive taste might be justified on grounds of responsibility
In defence of cosmopolitanism
David Miller has objected to the cosmopolitan argument that it is arbitrary and hence unfair to treat individuals differently on account of things for which they are not responsible. Such a view seems to require, implausibly, that individuals be treated identically even where (unchosen) needs differ. The objection is, however, inapplicable where the focus of cosmopolitan concern is arbitrary disadvantage rather than arbitrary treatment. This 'unfair disadvantage argument' supports a form of global luck egalitarianism. Miller also objects that cosmopolitanism is unable to accommodate special obligations generated by national membership. Cosmopolitanism can, however, accommodate many special obligations to compatriots. Those which it cannot accommodate are only morally compelling if we assume what the objection claims to prove - that cosmopolitanism is mistaken. Cosmopolitanism construed as global luck egalitarianism is therefore able to withstand both of Miller's objections, and has significant independent appeal on account of the unfair disadvantage argument
Describing equality
An earlier version of this article was presented to the Historical, International, Normative Theory (HINT) group at the University of Glasgow. I would like to thank the participants on that occasion, and also Richard Arneson, Jonathan Quong, Hillel Steiner, Stephen de Wijze and an anonymous referee for their helpful written comments. Research for the article was supported by the Arts and Humanities Research Council
- âŠ