8 research outputs found
How persuaded are you? A typology of responses
Several recent studies have suggested that there are two different ways in which a person
can proceed when assessing the persuasiveness of a mathematical argument: by
evaluating whether it is personally convincing, or by evaluating whether it is publicly
acceptable. In this paper, using Toulminâs (1958) argumentation scheme, we produce a
more detailed theoretical classification of the ways in which participants can interpret a
request to assess the persuasiveness of an argument. We suggest that there are (at least)
five ways in which such a question can be interpreted. The classification is illustrated
with data from a study that asked undergraduate students and research-active
mathematicians to rate how persuasive they found a given argument. We conclude by
arguing that researchers interested in mathematical conviction and proof validation need
to be aware of the different ways in which participants can interpret questions about the
persuasiveness of arguments, and that they must carefully control for these variations
during their studies
Functional explanation in mathematics
Mathematical explanations are poorly understood. Although mathematicians seem to regularly suggest that some proofs are explanatory whereas others are not, none of the philosophical accounts of what such claims mean has become widely accepted. In this paper we explore Wilkenfeldâs (2014, Synthese, 191, 3367-3391) suggestion that explanations are those sorts of things that (in the right circumstances, and in the right manner) generate understanding. By considering a basic model of human cognitive architecture, we suggest that existing accounts of mathematical explanation are all derivable consequences of Wilkenfeldâs âfunctional explanationâ proposal. We therefore argue that the explanatory criteria offered by earlier accounts can all be thought of as features that make it more likely that a mathematical proof will generate understanding. On the functional account, features such as characterising properties, unification, and salience correlate with explanatoriness, but they do not define explanatoriness
Semantic contamination and mathematical proof: can a non-proof prove?
The way words are used in natural language can influence how the same words are understood
by students in formal educational contexts. Hereweargue that this so-called semantic
contamination effect plays a role in determining how students engage with mathematical
proof, a fundamental aspect of learning mathematics. Analyses of responses to argument
evaluation tasks suggest that students may hold two different and contradictory conceptions
of proof: one related to conviction, and one to validity. We demonstrate that these
two conceptions can be preferentially elicited by making apparently irrelevant linguistic
changes to task instructions. After analyzing the occurrence of âproofâ and âproveâ in natural
language, we report two experiments that suggest that the noun form privileges evaluations
related to validity, and that the verb form privileges evaluations related to conviction.
In short, we show that (what is judged to be) a non-proof can sometimes (be judged to)
prove
âExplanatoryâ talk in mathematics research papers
In this paper we explore the ways in which mathematicians talk about explanation in their research papers. We analyze the use of the words explain/explanation (and various related words) in a large corpus of text containing research papers in both mathematics and physical sciences. We found that mathematicians do not frequently use this family of words and that their use is considerably more prevalent in physics papers than in mathematics papers. In particular, we found that physicists talk about explaining why disproportionately more often than mathematicians. We discuss some possible accounts for these differences
The effect of authority on the persuasiveness of mathematical arguments
Three experiments are reported which investigate the extent to which an authority figure
influences the level of persuasion undergraduate students and research-active mathematicians
invest in mathematical arguments. We demonstrate that, in some situations, both students and
researchers rate arguments as being more persuasive when they are associated with an expert
mathematician than when the author is anonymous. We develop a model which accounts for
these data by suggesting that, for both students and researchers, an authority figure only plays a
role when there is already some uncertainty about the argumentâs mathematical status.
Implications for pedagogy, and for future research, are discussed
How mathematicians obtain conviction: implications for mathematics instruction and research on epistemic cognition
The received view of mathematical practice is that mathematicians gain
certainty in mathematical assertions by deductive evidence rather than empirical or
authoritarian evidence. This assumption has influenced mathematics instruction where
students are expected to justify assertions with deductive arguments rather than by
checking the assertion with specific examples or appealing to authorities. In this paper,
we argue that the received view about mathematical practice is too simplistic; some
mathematicians sometimes gain high levels of conviction with empirical or authoritarian
evidence and sometimes do not gain full conviction from the proofs that they read. We
discuss what implications this might have, both for for mathematics instruction and
theories of epistemic cognition
Comparing expert and learner mathematical language: A corpus linguistics approach
Corpus linguists attempt to understand language by statistically analyzing large collections of text, known as corpora. We describe the creation of three corpora designed to enable the study of expert and learner mathematical language. Our corpora were formed by collecting and processing three different genres of mathematical texts: mathematical research papers,
undergraduate-level textbooks, and undergraduate dissertations. We pay particular attention to the method by which our corpora were created, and present a mechanism by which LaTeX source files can be easily converted to a form suitable for use with corpus analysis software packages. We then compare these three different types of mathematical texts by analyzing their word frequency distributions. We find that undergraduate students write in remarkably similar ways to textbook authors, but that research papers are substantially different. These differences are discussed
On mathematicians' different standards when evaluating elementary proofs
In this article, we report a study in which 109 research-active mathematicians were asked to judge the validity of a purported proof in undergraduate calculus. Significant results from our study were as follows: (a) there was substantial disagreement among mathematicians regarding whether the argument was a valid proof, (b) applied mathematicians were more likely than pure mathematicians to judge the argument valid, (c) participants who judged the argument invalid were more confident in their judgments than those who judged it valid, and (d) participants who judged the argument valid usually did not change their judgment when presented with a reason raised by other mathematicians for why the proof should be judged invalid. These findings suggest that, contrary to some claims in the literature, there is not a single standard of validity among contemporary mathematicians