7 research outputs found
The Local versus the Global in the History of Relativity: The Case of Belgium
This article contributes to a global history of relativity, by exploring how
Einstein's theory was appropriated in Belgium. This may sound as a
contradiction in terms, yet the early-twentieth-century Belgian context,
because of its cultural diversity and reflectiveness of global conditions (the
principal example being the First World War), proves well-suited to expose
transnational flows and patterns in the global history of relativity. The
attempts of Belgian physicist Th\'eophile de Donder to contribute to relativity
physics during the 1910s and 1920s illustrate the role of the war in shaping
the transnational networks through which relativity circulated. The local
attitudes of conservative Belgian Catholic scientists and philosophers, who
denied that relativity was philosophically significant, exemplify a global
pattern: while critics of relativity feared to become marginalized by the
scientific, political, and cultural revolutions that Einstein and his theory
were taken to represent, supporters sympathized with these revolutions
How "Facts" Shaped Modern Disciplines: The Fluid Concept of Fact and the Common Origins of German Physics and Historiography
This history of the concept of fact reveals that the fact-oriented practices
of German physicists and historians derived from common origins. The concept of
fact became part of the German language remarkably late. It gained momentum
only toward the end of the eighteenth century. I show that the concept of fact
emerged as part of a historical knowledge tradition, which comprised both human
and natural empirical study. Around 1800, parts of this tradition, including
the concept of fact, were integrated into the epistemological basis of several
emerging disciplines, including physics and historiography. During this process
of discipline formation, the concept of fact remained fluid. I reveal this
fluidity by unearthing different interpretations and roles of facts in
different German contexts around 1800. I demonstrate how a fact-based
epistemology emerged at the University of G\"ottingen in the late eighteenth
century, by focusing on universal historian August Ludwig Schl\"ozer and the
experimentalist Georg Christoph Lichtenberg. In a time of scientific and
political revolutions, they regarded facts as eternal knowledge, contrasting
them with short-lived theories and speculations. Remarkably, Schl\"ozer and
Lichtenberg construed facts as the basis of Wissenschaft, but not as
Wissenschaft itself. Only after 1800, empirically minded German physicists and
historians granted facts self-contained value. As physics and historiography
became institutionalized at German universities, the concept of fact acquired
different interpretations in different disciplinary settings. These related to
fact-oriented research practices, such as precision measurement in physics and
source criticism in historiography
History as a Tool for Natural Science: How Ernst Mach Applied Historical Methods to Physics
Historical methods have long been put to use in the making of natural knowledge. In this article, I examine the use of historical methods by nineteenth-century physicists, focusing on the Austrian researcher Ernst Mach in particular. I argue that Mach applied methods characteristic of the then-dominant historical and philological disciplines to his own discipline of physics. He construed history as a tool for the physicist. On the basis of a study of his notebooks and correspondence with the chemist-turned-historian Emil    Wohlwill, I explain what he sought to achieve by means of this tool, and reconstruct the practices characterizing his historical research. These practices included the reading, ordering, and comparison of textual sources. Moreover, Mach appropriated the historical-philological method of source criticism. I show that prominent fellow physicists of Mach, including Johann Poggendorff and Hermann von Helmholtz, made use of similar historical methods, even though their aims were different. Together, the cases of these history-writing physicists illustrate how history and natural science continued to intertwine in a time of increasing disciplinary fragmentation
The Local versus the Global in the History of Relativity: The Case of Belgium
This article contributes to a global history of relativity, by exploring how Einstein’s theory was appropriated in Belgium. This may sound as a contradiction in terms, yet the early-twentiethcentury Belgian context, because of its cultural diversity and reflectiveness of global conditions (the
principal example being the First World War), proves well-suited to expose transnational flows and patterns in the global history of relativity. The attempts of Belgian physicist Théophile de Donder to contribute to relativity physics during the 1910s and 1920s illustrate the role of the war in shaping the transnational networks through which relativity circulated. The local attitudes of conservative Belgian Catholic scientists and philosophers, who denied that relativity was philosophically significant, exemplify a global pattern: while critics of relativity feared to become marginalized by the scientific,political, and cultural revolutions that Einstein and his theory were taken to represent, supporters sympathized with these revolutions
The Concept of Fact in German Physics around 1900: A Comparison between Mach and Einstein
The concept of fact has a history. Over the past centuries, physicists have
appropriated it in various ways. In this article, we compare Ernst Mach and
Albert Einstein's interpretations of the concept. Mach, like most
nineteenth-century physicists, contrasted fact and theory. He understood facts
as real and complex combinations of natural events. Theories, in turn, only
served to order and communicate facts efficiently. Einstein's concept of fact
was incompatible with Mach's, since Einstein believed facts could be
theoretical too, just as he ascribed mathematical theorizing a leading role in
representing reality. For example, he used the concept of fact to refer to a
generally valid result of experience. The differences we disclose between Mach
and Einstein were symbolic for broader tensions in the German physics
discipline. Furthermore, they underline the historically fluid character of the
category of the fact, both within physics and beyond.Comment: Physics in Perspective, 202
Neither slim nor fat: estimating the mass of the dodo (Raphus cucullatus, Aves, Columbiformes) based on the largest sample of dodo bones to date
The dodo (Raphus cucullatus) might be the most enigmatic bird of all times. It is, therefore, highly remarkable that no consensus has yet been reached on its body mass; previous scientific estimates of its mass vary by more than 100%. Until now, the vast amount of bones stored at the Natural History Museum in Mauritius has not yet been studied morphometrically nor in relation to body mass. Here, a new estimate of the dodo’s mass is presented based on the largest sample of dodo femora ever measured (n = 174). In order to do this, we have used the regression method and chosen our variables based on biological, mathematical and physical arguments. The results indicate that the mean mass of the dodo was circa 12 kg, which is approximately five times as heavy as the largest living Columbidae (pigeons and doves), the clade to which the dodo belongs