2,645 research outputs found
Just Two Nonorthogonal Quantum States
From the perspective of quantum information theory, a system so simple as one
restricted to just two nonorthogonal states can be surprisingly rich in
physics. In this paper, we explore the extent of this statement through a
review of three topics: (1) ``nonlocality without entanglement'' as exhibited
in binary quantum communication channels, (2) the tradeoff between information
gain and state disturbance for two prescribed states, and (3) the quantitative
clonability of those states. Each topic in its own way quantifies the extent to
which two states are ``quantum'' with respect to each other, i.e., the extent
to which the two together violate some classical precept. It is suggested that
even toy examples such as these hold some promise for shedding light on the
foundations of quantum theory.Comment: 7 pages, no figures, requires myplenumQPH.st
Quantum Bayesianism at the Perimeter
The author summarizes the Quantum Bayesian viewpoint of quantum mechanics,
developed originally by C. M. Caves, R. Schack, and himself. It is a view
crucially dependent upon the tools of quantum information theory. Work at the
Perimeter Institute for Theoretical Physics continues the development and is
focused on the hard technical problem of a finding a good representation of
quantum mechanics purely in terms of probabilities, without amplitudes or
Hilbert-space operators. The best candidate representation involves a
mysterious entity called a symmetric informationally complete quantum
measurement. Contemplation of it gives a way of thinking of the Born Rule as an
addition to the rules of probability theory, applicable when one gambles on the
consequences of interactions with physical systems. The article ends by
outlining some directions for future work.Comment: 6 pages, 2 figures; an abridged version of this will appear in
Physics in Canada
Interview with a Quantum Bayesian
This paper collects into one place (most of) my answers to the questions
Maximilian Schlosshauer posed in his interview volume, "Elegance and Enigma:
The Quantum Interviews" (Springer, Frontiers Collection, 2011).Comment: 22 page
Copenhagen Interpretation Delenda Est?
This is a slightly extended version of a review of Adam Becker's book What is
Real? The Unfinished Quest for the Meaning of Quantum Physics, to appear in
American Journal of Physics. The key addition is the reference list.Comment: 6 page
On Participatory Realism
In the Philosophical Investigations, Ludwig Wittgenstein wrote, " 'I' is not
the name of a person, nor 'here' of a place, .... But they are connected with
names. ... [And] it is characteristic of physics not to use these words." This
statement expresses the dominant way of thinking in physics: Physics is about
the impersonal laws of nature; the "I" never makes an appearance in it. Since
the advent of quantum theory, however, there has always been a nagging pressure
to insert a first-person perspective into the heart of physics. In incarnations
of lesser or greater strength, one may consider the "Copenhagen" views of Bohr,
Heisenberg, and Pauli, the observer-participator view of John Wheeler, the
informational interpretation of Anton Zeilinger and Caslav Brukner, the
relational interpretation of Carlo Rovelli, and, most radically, the QBism of
N. David Mermin, Ruediger Schack, and the present author, as acceding to the
pressure. These views have lately been termed "participatory realism" to
emphasize that rather than relinquishing the idea of reality (as they are often
accused of), they are saying that reality is more than any third-person
perspective can capture. Thus, far from instances of instrumentalism or
antirealism, these views of quantum theory should be regarded as attempts to
make a deep statement about the nature of reality. This paper explicates the
idea for the case of QBism. As well, it highlights the influence of John
Wheeler's "law without law" on QBism's formulation.Comment: 23 pages, to appear in "Information & Interaction: Eddington,
Wheeler, and the Limits of Knowledge", edited by Ian T. Durham and Dean
Rickles; v3 corrects word omissions from the Wheeler notebook page
Notwithstanding Bohr, the Reasons for QBism
Without Niels Bohr, QBism would be nothing. But QBism is not Bohr. This paper
attempts to show that, despite a popular misconception, QBism is no minor tweak
to Bohr's interpretation of quantum mechanics. It is something quite distinct.
Along the way, we lay out three tenets of QBism in some detail: 1) The Born
Rule---the foundation of what quantum theory means for QBism---is a normative
statement. It is about the decision-making behavior any individual agent should
strive for; it is not a descriptive "law of nature" in the usual sense. 2) All
probabilities, including all quantum probabilities, are so subjective they
never tell nature what to do. This includes probability-1 assignments. Quantum
states thus have no "ontic hold" on the world. 3) Quantum measurement outcomes
just are personal experiences for the agent gambling upon them. Particularly,
quantum measurement outcomes are not, to paraphrase Bohr, instances of
"irreversible amplification in devices whose design is communicable in common
language suitably refined by the terminology of classical physics." Finally, an
explicit comparison is given between QBism and Bohr with regard to three
subjects: a) The issue of the "detached observer" as it arose in a debate
between Pauli and Bohr, b) Bohr's reply to Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen, and
c) Bohr's mature notion of "quantum phenomena." At the end, we discuss how
Bohr's notion of phenomena may have something to offer the philosophy of
William James: A physics from which to further develop his vision of the
world---call it an ontology if you will---in which "new being comes in local
spots and patches."Comment: 44 pages, 1 figur
Quantum Mechanics as Quantum Information (and only a little more)
In this paper, I try once again to cause some good-natured trouble. The issue
remains, when will we ever stop burdening the taxpayer with conferences devoted
to the quantum foundations? The suspicion is expressed that no end will be in
sight until a means is found to reduce quantum theory to two or three
statements of crisp physical (rather than abstract, axiomatic) significance. In
this regard, no tool appears better calibrated for a direct assault than
quantum information theory. Far from a strained application of the latest fad
to a time-honored problem, this method holds promise precisely because a large
part--but not all--of the structure of quantum theory has always concerned
information. It is just that the physics community needs reminding.
This paper, though taking quant-ph/0106166 as its core, corrects one mistake
and offers several observations beyond the previous version. In particular, I
identify one element of quantum mechanics that I would not label a subjective
term in the theory--it is the integer parameter D traditionally ascribed to a
quantum system via its Hilbert-space dimension.Comment: 59 pages, 5 figures, 140 equations, one simple ide
The Anti-Vaxjo Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics
In this note, I try to accomplish two things. First, I fulfill Andrei
Khrennikov's request that I comment on his "Vaxjo Interpretation of Quantum
Mechanics," contrasting it with my own present view of the subject matter.
Second, I try to paint an image of the hopeful vistas an information-based
conception of quantum mechanics indicates.Comment: 18 pages, not one equation. Requires sprocl.st
QBism, the Perimeter of Quantum Bayesianism
This article summarizes the Quantum Bayesian point of view of quantum
mechanics, with special emphasis on the view's outer edges---dubbed QBism.
QBism has its roots in personalist Bayesian probability theory, is crucially
dependent upon the tools of quantum information theory, and most recently, has
set out to investigate whether the physical world might be of a type sketched
by some false-started philosophies of 100 years ago (pragmatism, pluralism,
nonreductionism, and meliorism). Beyond conceptual issues, work at Perimeter
Institute is focused on the hard technical problem of finding a good
representation of quantum mechanics purely in terms of probabilities, without
amplitudes or Hilbert-space operators. The best candidate representation
involves a mysterious entity called a symmetric informationally complete
quantum measurement. Contemplation of it gives a way of thinking of the Born
Rule as an addition to the rules of probability theory, applicable when an
agent considers gambling on the consequences of his interactions with a newly
recognized universal capacity: dimension (formerly Hilbert-space dimension).
(The word "capacity" should conjure up an image of something like gravitational
mass---a body's mass measures its capacity to attract other bodies. With
hindsight one can say that the founders of quantum mechanics discovered another
universal capacity, "dimension.") The article ends by showing that the
egocentric elements in QBism represent no impediment to pursuing quantum
cosmology and outlining some directions for future work.Comment: 30 pages, 6 figure
Information Gain vs. State Disturbance in Quantum Theory
The engine that powers quantum cryptography is the principle that there are
no physical means for gathering information about the identity of a quantum
system's state (when it is known to be prepared in one of a set of
nonorthogonal states) without disturbing the system in a statistically
detectable way. This situation is often mistakenly described as a consequence
of the ``Heisenberg uncertainty principle.'' A more accurate account is that it
is a unique feature of quantum phenomena that rests ultimately on the Hilbert
space structure of the theory along with the fact that time evolutions for
isolated systems are unitary. In this paper I explore several aspects of the
``information / disturbance principle'' in an attempt to make it firmly
quantitative for both pure and mixed states. The final section briefly explores
the extent to which such a principle can be taken as a foundation for unitary
dynamics rather than as a consequence.Comment: 5 pages LaTeX, Extended Abstract for PhysComp96, requires
pac96sty.te
- …