16 research outputs found

    Effects of fluoxetine on functional outcomes after acute stroke (FOCUS): a pragmatic, double-blind, randomised, controlled trial

    Get PDF
    Background Results of small trials indicate that fluoxetine might improve functional outcomes after stroke. The FOCUS trial aimed to provide a precise estimate of these effects. Methods FOCUS was a pragmatic, multicentre, parallel group, double-blind, randomised, placebo-controlled trial done at 103 hospitals in the UK. Patients were eligible if they were aged 18 years or older, had a clinical stroke diagnosis, were enrolled and randomly assigned between 2 days and 15 days after onset, and had focal neurological deficits. Patients were randomly allocated fluoxetine 20 mg or matching placebo orally once daily for 6 months via a web-based system by use of a minimisation algorithm. The primary outcome was functional status, measured with the modified Rankin Scale (mRS), at 6 months. Patients, carers, health-care staff, and the trial team were masked to treatment allocation. Functional status was assessed at 6 months and 12 months after randomisation. Patients were analysed according to their treatment allocation. This trial is registered with the ISRCTN registry, number ISRCTN83290762. Findings Between Sept 10, 2012, and March 31, 2017, 3127 patients were recruited. 1564 patients were allocated fluoxetine and 1563 allocated placebo. mRS data at 6 months were available for 1553 (99·3%) patients in each treatment group. The distribution across mRS categories at 6 months was similar in the fluoxetine and placebo groups (common odds ratio adjusted for minimisation variables 0·951 [95% CI 0·839–1·079]; p=0·439). Patients allocated fluoxetine were less likely than those allocated placebo to develop new depression by 6 months (210 [13·43%] patients vs 269 [17·21%]; difference 3·78% [95% CI 1·26–6·30]; p=0·0033), but they had more bone fractures (45 [2·88%] vs 23 [1·47%]; difference 1·41% [95% CI 0·38–2·43]; p=0·0070). There were no significant differences in any other event at 6 or 12 months. Interpretation Fluoxetine 20 mg given daily for 6 months after acute stroke does not seem to improve functional outcomes. Although the treatment reduced the occurrence of depression, it increased the frequency of bone fractures. These results do not support the routine use of fluoxetine either for the prevention of post-stroke depression or to promote recovery of function. Funding UK Stroke Association and NIHR Health Technology Assessment Programme

    PhĂ©nomĂ©nologie de l’humour

    No full text
    Dans cet article, nous dressons un inventaire des phĂ©nomĂšnes qu’une thĂ©orie de l’humour devrait expliquer. La premiĂšre partie fait valoir que l’humour est une propriĂ©tĂ© qui s’attache Ă  certains Ă©vĂ©nements mentaux, plutĂŽt qu’à certains objets du monde (les blagues, par exemple). Nous signalons l’une des consĂ©quences de ce fait : les blagues, prises isolĂ©ment, ne sont pas un phĂ©nomĂšne universel. Nous suggĂ©rons Ă©galement que, mĂȘme s’il se peut que certaines formes de rire soient dĂ©clenchĂ©es par des situations qui n’ont rien d’humoristique, il existe un lien spĂ©cial entre le rire dit « de Duchenne » et un certain type de stimulation cognitive propre Ă  le dĂ©clencher. Nous poursuivons en montrant que le sentiment d’allĂ©gresse associĂ© au rire (sentiment qui constitue pour nous un aspect crucial du rire) est un phĂ©nomĂšne psychologique qui se prĂȘte Ă  une approche « hĂ©tĂ©rophĂ©nomĂ©nologique ». L’hĂ©tĂ©rophĂ©nomĂ©nologie est une phĂ©nomĂ©nologie qui envisage les Ă©tats subjectifs en tant que donnĂ©es Ă  expliquer, mais pas nĂ©cessairement en tant qu’interprĂ©tations valides des phĂ©nomĂšnes psychologiques qui les sous-tendent. Selon nous, ce sentiment d’allĂ©gresse liĂ© Ă  l’humour est Ă©troitement liĂ© Ă  un autre sentiment : le sentiment du cocasse qui nous saisit face Ă  des phĂ©nomĂšnes incongrus. Les liens qui unissent ces deux Ă©motions sont riches d’enseignements pour toute thĂ©orie de l’humour. La derniĂšre partie passe en revue, en plus des divers cahiers des charges dressĂ©s par des thĂ©ories de l’humour antĂ©rieures, quelques dĂ©couvertes issues de ces travaux et de certains autres.In this article, we develop an inventory of the explananda that any complete theory of humor should account for. In the first chapter, we argue that humor is a property of events in the mind, rather than objects in the world (such as jokes), and we point out that a result of this is that individual jokes are not universal. We also suggest that while some varieties of laughter may be triggered by situations that are not humorous in any sense, a special connection exists between Duchenne-type laughter and the certain type of cognitive stimulation that usually elicits it. Then we argue that the feeling of mirth — perhaps the most central aspect of humor — is a psychological phenomena that should be explored by means of a “heterophenomenological” approach — one that uses subjective states as data to be explained, but not necessarily as valid interpretations of the underlying psychological phenomena. And we comment that this feeling (“funny” — humorous) is closely related to another feeling: “funny” — odd — a relationship worth exploring in any theory of humor. In the second chapter, we catalogue the findings of these explorations and others, in addition to those further explananda highlighted by previous theories of humor

    Rires

    No full text
    Rire, mais comment et pourquoi? Le rire peut ĂȘtre formel, joyeux, mĂ©prisant, nerveux ou embarrassĂ©... Il peut ĂȘtre aussi un moyen de dĂ©dramatiser des situations de violence, de prendre contact ou de garder ses distances avec l’autre et, surtout, de montrer son intĂ©gration Ă  une communautĂ©. Universel qui n’appartiendrait qu’aux ĂȘtres humains, le rire nĂ©cessite de comprendre les intentions de celui qui vous fait face, d’ĂȘtre un acteur social Ă  part entiĂšre. Les auteurs de ce nouveau numĂ©ro de la revue Terrain s’attachent Ă  dĂ©crire cette pratique dans diffĂ©rents contextes culturels, esquissant les contours d’une vĂ©ritable anthropologie du rire

    A short history of evolutionary theory Uma breve histĂłria da teoria evolutiva

    No full text
    The history of the Theory of Evolution has been told a number of times by historians, philosophers, professors, writers, scientists and so on. However, many of these versions differ from or even contradict one another. In this article, the history of the Theory of Evolution is retold according to a dialectical-materialistic perspective. It analyzes the historical contradictions between Darwinian evolution theory and Mendel's model, the background that led to the synthetic theory of evolution, the debate carried out by classic schools and the result of synthesis, as well as the still current debate between Neutralism and Selectionism. Finally, it also discusses the interpretative model used ("an idiosyncratic dialectic materialism"), mainly in relation with Popper's and Kuhn's models.<br>A histĂłria da teoria evolutiva tem sito contada inĂșmeras vezes por historiadores, filĂłsofos, professores, escritores, cientistas etc. Contudo, muitas destas versĂ”es diferem entre si ou mesmo se contradizem. Neste trabalho, a histĂłria da teoria evolutiva Ă© recontada a partir de uma perspectiva materialista dialĂ©tica. SĂŁo analisadas as contradiçÔes histĂłricas entre a teoria evolutiva darwiniana e o modelo mendeliano, o caminho para a teoria sintĂ©tica da evolução, o debate entre as escolas clĂĄssica e do balanco que sucedeu a sĂ­ntese, bem como o debate, ainda atual, entre neutralismo e selecionismo. Ao final, o modelo interpretativo utilizado ("um materialismo dialĂ©tico idiossincrĂĄtico") Ă© discutido, principalmente, em relação aos modelos popperiano e kuhniano
    corecore