3,341 research outputs found
The âGalilean Style in Scienceâ and the Inconsistency of Linguistic Theorising
Chomskyâs principle of epistemological tolerance says that in theoretical linguistics contradictions between the data and the hypotheses may be temporarily tolerated in order to protect the explanatory power of the theory. The paper raises the following problem: What kinds of contradictions may be tolerated between the data and the hypotheses in theoretical linguistics? First a model of paraconsistent logic is introduced which differentiates between week and strong contradiction. As a second step, a case study is carried out which exemplifies that the principle of epistemological tolerance may be interpreted as the tolerance of week contradiction. The third step of the argumentation focuses on another case study which exemplifies that the principle of epistemological tolerance must not be interpreted as the tolerance of strong contradiction. The reason for the latter insight is the unreliability and the uncertainty of introspective data. From this finding the author draws the conclusion that it is the integration of different data types that may lead to the improvement of current theoretical linguistics and that the integration of different data types requires a novel methodology which, for the time being, is not available
The âGalilean Style in Scienceâ and the Inconsistency of Linguistic Theorising
Chomskyâs principle of epistemological tolerance says that in theoretical linguistics contradictions between the data and the hypotheses may be temporarily tolerated in order to protect the explanatory power of the theory. The paper raises the following problem: What kinds of contradictions may be tolerated between the data and the hypotheses in theoretical linguistics? First a model of paraconsistent logic is introduced which differentiates between week and strong contradiction. As a second step, a case study is carried out which exemplifies that the principle of epistemological tolerance may be interpreted as the tolerance of week contradiction. The third step of the argumentation focuses on another case study which exemplifies that the principle of epistemological tolerance must not be interpreted as the tolerance of strong contradiction. The reason for the latter insight is the unreliability and the uncertainty of introspective data. From this finding the author draws the conclusion that it is the integration of different data types that may lead to the improvement of current theoretical linguistics and that the integration of different data types requires a novel methodology which, for the time being, is not available
Recommended from our members
Spring School on Language, Music, and Cognition: Organizing Events in Time
The interdisciplinary spring school âLanguage, music, and cognition: Organizing events in timeâ was held from February 26 to March 2, 2018 at the Institute of Musicology of the University of Cologne. Language, speech, and music as events in time were explored from different perspectives including evolutionary biology, social cognition, developmental psychology, cognitive neuroscience of speech, language, and communication, as well as computational and biological approaches to language and music. There were 10 lectures, 4 workshops, and 1 student poster session.
Overall, the spring school investigated language and music as neurocognitive systems and focused on a mechanistic approach exploring the neural substrates underlying musical, linguistic, social, and emotional processes and behaviors. In particular, researchers approached questions concerning cognitive processes, computational procedures, and neural mechanisms underlying the temporal organization of language and music, mainly from two perspectives: one was concerned with syntax or structural representations of language and music as neurocognitive systems (i.e., an intrapersonal perspective), while the other emphasized social interaction and emotions in their communicative function (i.e., an interpersonal perspective). The spring school not only acted as a platform for knowledge transfer and exchange but also generated a number of important research questions as challenges for future investigations
Recommended from our members
Coargumenthood and the processing of pronouns
We report three eye-movement experiments and an offline task investigating structural constraints on pronoun resolution in different contexts. This included âcoargumentâ contexts in which a pronoun was the direct object of a verb (âThe surgeon remembered that Jonathan had noticed himâ), so-called picture noun phrases (âThe surgeon remembered that Jonathan had a picture of himâ) and picture noun phrases with a possessor (âThe surgeon remembered about Jonathanâs picture of himâ). In each eye-movement experiment, we observed longer reading times when the nonlocal antecedent (âthe surgeonâ) mismatched in stereotypical gender with the pronoun, but little evidence of the gender of the local antecedent (âJonathanâ) influencing reading times. The offline task suggested readers occasionally interpret pronouns as referring to local antecedents, especially in non-coargument contexts. These results suggest that structural constraints constitute more highly weighted cues to antecedent retrieval than gender congruency during the initial stages of memory retrieval during pronoun resolution
Relinquishing Control: What Romanian De Se Attitude Reports Teach Us About Immunity To Error Through Misidentification
Higginbotham argued that certain linguistic items of English, when used in indirect discourse, necessarily trigger first-personal interpretations. They are: the emphatic reflexive pronoun and the controlled understood subject, represented as PRO. PRO is special, in this respect, due to its imposing obligatory control effects between the main clause and its subordinates ). Folescu & Higginbotham, in addition, argued that in Romanian, a language whose grammar doesnât assign a prominent role to PRO, de se triggers are correlated with the subjunctive mood of certain verbs. That paper, however, didnât account for the grammatical diversity of the reports that display immunity to error through misidentification in Romanian: some of these reports are expressed by using de se triggers; others are not. Their IEM, moreover, is not systematically lexically controlled by the verbs, via their theta-roles; it is, rather, determined by the meaning of the verbs in question. Given the data from Romanian, I will argue, the phenomenon of IEM cannot be fully explained starting either from the syntactical or the lexical structure of a language
Syntax-semantics interface: an algebraic model
We extend our formulation of Merge and Minimalism in terms of Hopf algebras
to an algebraic model of a syntactic-semantic interface. We show that methods
adopted in the formulation of renormalization (extraction of meaningful
physical values) in theoretical physics are relevant to describe the extraction
of meaning from syntactic expressions. We show how this formulation relates to
computational models of semantics and we answer some recent controversies about
implications for generative linguistics of the current functioning of large
language models.Comment: LaTeX, 75 pages, 19 figure
Old and New Minimalism: a Hopf algebra comparison
In this paper we compare some old formulations of Minimalism, in particular
Stabler's computational minimalism, and Chomsky's new formulation of Merge and
Minimalism, from the point of view of their mathematical description in terms
of Hopf algebras. We show that the newer formulation has a clear advantage
purely in terms of the underlying mathematical structure. More precisely, in
the case of Stabler's computational minimalism, External Merge can be described
in terms of a partially defined operated algebra with binary operation, while
Internal Merge determines a system of right-ideal coideals of the Loday-Ronco
Hopf algebra and corresponding right-module coalgebra quotients. This
mathematical structure shows that Internal and External Merge have
significantly different roles in the old formulations of Minimalism, and they
are more difficult to reconcile as facets of a single algebraic operation, as
desirable linguistically. On the other hand, we show that the newer formulation
of Minimalism naturally carries a Hopf algebra structure where Internal and
External Merge directly arise from the same operation. We also compare, at the
level of algebraic properties, the externalization model of the new Minimalism
with proposals for assignments of planar embeddings based on heads of trees.Comment: 27 pages, LaTeX, 3 figure
Optimality Theory as a Framework for Lexical Acquisition
This paper re-investigates a lexical acquisition system initially developed
for French.We show that, interestingly, the architecture of the system
reproduces and implements the main components of Optimality Theory. However, we
formulate the hypothesis that some of its limitations are mainly due to a poor
representation of the constraints used. Finally, we show how a better
representation of the constraints used would yield better results
Troubles with Bayesianism: An introduction to the psychological immune system
A Bayesian mind is, at its core, a rational mind. Bayesianism is thus well-suited to predict and explain mental processes that best exemplify our ability to be rational. However, evidence from belief acquisition and change appears to show that we do not acquire and update information in a Bayesian way. Instead, the principles of belief acquisition and updating seem grounded in maintaining a psychological immune system rather than in approximating
a Bayesian processor
Linearly bounded infinite graphs
Linearly bounded Turing machines have been mainly studied as acceptors for
context-sensitive languages. We define a natural class of infinite automata
representing their observable computational behavior, called linearly bounded
graphs. These automata naturally accept the same languages as the linearly
bounded machines defining them. We present some of their structural properties
as well as alternative characterizations in terms of rewriting systems and
context-sensitive transductions. Finally, we compare these graphs to rational
graphs, which are another class of automata accepting the context-sensitive
languages, and prove that in the bounded-degree case, rational graphs are a
strict sub-class of linearly bounded graphs
- âŠ