756 research outputs found

    Type classes for efficient exact real arithmetic in Coq

    Get PDF
    Floating point operations are fast, but require continuous effort on the part of the user in order to ensure that the results are correct. This burden can be shifted away from the user by providing a library of exact analysis in which the computer handles the error estimates. Previously, we [Krebbers/Spitters 2011] provided a fast implementation of the exact real numbers in the Coq proof assistant. Our implementation improved on an earlier implementation by O'Connor by using type classes to describe an abstract specification of the underlying dense set from which the real numbers are built. In particular, we used dyadic rationals built from Coq's machine integers to obtain a 100 times speed up of the basic operations already. This article is a substantially expanded version of [Krebbers/Spitters 2011] in which the implementation is extended in the various ways. First, we implement and verify the sine and cosine function. Secondly, we create an additional implementation of the dense set based on Coq's fast rational numbers. Thirdly, we extend the hierarchy to capture order on undecidable structures, while it was limited to decidable structures before. This hierarchy, based on type classes, allows us to share theory on the naturals, integers, rationals, dyadics, and reals in a convenient way. Finally, we obtain another dramatic speed-up by avoiding evaluation of termination proofs at runtime.Comment: arXiv admin note: text overlap with arXiv:1105.275

    Proving Induction

    Get PDF
    The hard problem of induction is to argue without begging the question that inductive inference, applied properly in the proper circumstances, is conducive to truth. A recent theorem seems to show that the hard problem has a deductive solution. The theorem, provable in ZFC, states that a predictive function M exists with the following property: whatever world we live in, M ncorrectly predicts the world’s present state given its previous states at all times apart from a well-ordered subset. On the usual model of time a well-ordered subset is small relative to the set of all times. M’s existence therefore seems to provide a solution to the hard problem. My paper argues for two conclusions. First, the theorem does not solve the hard problem of induction. More positively though, it solves a version of the problem in which the structure of time is given modulo our choice of set theory

    Reflections on Mathematical Economics in the Algorithmic Mode

    Get PDF
    Non-standard analysis can be harnessed by the recursion theorist. But as a computable economist, the conundrums of the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem and the associated Skolem paradox, seem to pose insurmountable epistemological difficulties against the use of algorithmic non-standard analysis. Discontinuities can be tamed by recursive analysis. This particular kind of taming may be a way out of the formidable obstacles created by the difficulties of Diophantine Decision Problems. Methods of existence proofs, used by the classical mathematician - even if not invoking the axiom of choice - cannot be shown to be equivalent to the exhibition of an instance in the sense of a constructive proof. These issues were prompted by the fertile and critical contributions to this special issue.

    Learning algebraic structures from text

    Get PDF
    AbstractThe present work investigates the learnability of classes of substructures of some algebraic structures: submonoids and subgroups of given groups, ideals of given commutative rings, subfields of given vector spaces. The learner sees all positive data but no negative one and converges to a program enumerating or computing the set to be learned. Besides semantical (BC) and syntactical (Ex) convergence also the more restrictive ordinal bounds on the number of mind changes are considered. The following is shown: (a) Learnability depends much on the amount of semantic knowledge given at the synthesis of the learner where this knowledge is represented by programs for the algebraic operations, codes for prominent elements of the algebraic structure (like 0 and 1 fields) and certain parameters (like the dimension of finite-dimensional vector spaces). For several natural examples, good knowledge of the semantics may enable to keep ordinal mind change bounds while restricted knowledge may either allow only BC-convergence or even not permit learnability at all.(b) The class of all ideals of a recursive ring is BC-learnable iff the ring is Noetherian. Furthermore, one has either only a BC-learner outputting enumerable indices or one can already get an Ex-learner converging to decision procedures and respecting an ordinal bound on the number of mind changes. The ring is Artinian iff the ideals can be Ex-learned with a constant bound on the number of mind changes, this constant is the length of the ring. Ex-learnability depends not only on the ring but also on the representation of the ring. Polynomial rings over the field of rationals with n variables have exactly the ordinal mind change bound ωn in the standard representation. Similar results can be established for unars. Noetherian unars with one function can be learned with an ordinal mind change bound aω for some a
    • …
    corecore