131,801 research outputs found

    First-Order Decomposition Trees

    Full text link
    Lifting attempts to speed up probabilistic inference by exploiting symmetries in the model. Exact lifted inference methods, like their propositional counterparts, work by recursively decomposing the model and the problem. In the propositional case, there exist formal structures, such as decomposition trees (dtrees), that represent such a decomposition and allow us to determine the complexity of inference a priori. However, there is currently no equivalent structure nor analogous complexity results for lifted inference. In this paper, we introduce FO-dtrees, which upgrade propositional dtrees to the first-order level. We show how these trees can characterize a lifted inference solution for a probabilistic logical model (in terms of a sequence of lifted operations), and make a theoretical analysis of the complexity of lifted inference in terms of the novel notion of lifted width for the tree

    Chain models, trees of singular cardinality and dynamic EF games

    Get PDF
    Let κ be a singular cardinal. Karp's notion of a chain model of size ? is defined to be an ordinary model of size κ along with a decomposition of it into an increasing union of length cf(κ). With a notion of satisfaction and (chain)-isomorphism such models give an infinitary logic largely mimicking first order logic. In this paper we associate to this logic a notion of a dynamic EF-game which gauges when two chain models are chain-isomorphic. To this game is associated a tree which is a tree of size κ with no κ-branches (even no cf(κ)-branches). The measure of how non-isomorphic the models are is reflected by a certain order on these trees, called reduction. We study the collection of trees of size κ with no κ-branches under this notion and prove that when cf(κ) = ω this collection is rather regular; in particular it has universality number exactly κ+. Such trees are then used to develop a descriptive set theory of the space cf(κ)κ.The main result of the paper gives in the case of κ strong limit singular an exact connection between the descriptive set-theoretic complexity of the chain isomorphism orbit of a model, the reduction order on the trees and winning strategies in the corresponding dynamic EF games. In particular we obtain a neat analog of the notion of Scott watershed from the Scott analysis of countable models

    Order Invariance on Decomposable Structures

    Full text link
    Order-invariant formulas access an ordering on a structure's universe, but the model relation is independent of the used ordering. Order invariance is frequently used for logic-based approaches in computer science. Order-invariant formulas capture unordered problems of complexity classes and they model the independence of the answer to a database query from low-level aspects of databases. We study the expressive power of order-invariant monadic second-order (MSO) and first-order (FO) logic on restricted classes of structures that admit certain forms of tree decompositions (not necessarily of bounded width). While order-invariant MSO is more expressive than MSO and, even, CMSO (MSO with modulo-counting predicates), we show that order-invariant MSO and CMSO are equally expressive on graphs of bounded tree width and on planar graphs. This extends an earlier result for trees due to Courcelle. Moreover, we show that all properties definable in order-invariant FO are also definable in MSO on these classes. These results are applications of a theorem that shows how to lift up definability results for order-invariant logics from the bags of a graph's tree decomposition to the graph itself.Comment: Accepted for LICS 201

    Eight-Fifth Approximation for TSP Paths

    Full text link
    We prove the approximation ratio 8/5 for the metric {s,t}\{s,t\}-path-TSP problem, and more generally for shortest connected TT-joins. The algorithm that achieves this ratio is the simple "Best of Many" version of Christofides' algorithm (1976), suggested by An, Kleinberg and Shmoys (2012), which consists in determining the best Christofides {s,t}\{s,t\}-tour out of those constructed from a family \Fscr_{>0} of trees having a convex combination dominated by an optimal solution x∗x^* of the fractional relaxation. They give the approximation guarantee 5+12\frac{\sqrt{5}+1}{2} for such an {s,t}\{s,t\}-tour, which is the first improvement after the 5/3 guarantee of Hoogeveen's Christofides type algorithm (1991). Cheriyan, Friggstad and Gao (2012) extended this result to a 13/8-approximation of shortest connected TT-joins, for ∣T∣≥4|T|\ge 4. The ratio 8/5 is proved by simplifying and improving the approach of An, Kleinberg and Shmoys that consists in completing x∗/2x^*/2 in order to dominate the cost of "parity correction" for spanning trees. We partition the edge-set of each spanning tree in \Fscr_{>0} into an {s,t}\{s,t\}-path (or more generally, into a TT-join) and its complement, which induces a decomposition of x∗x^*. This decomposition can be refined and then efficiently used to complete x∗/2x^*/2 without using linear programming or particular properties of TT, but by adding to each cut deficient for x∗/2x^*/2 an individually tailored explicitly given vector, inherent in x∗x^*. A simple example shows that the Best of Many Christofides algorithm may not find a shorter {s,t}\{s,t\}-tour than 3/2 times the incidentally common optima of the problem and of its fractional relaxation.Comment: 15 pages, corrected typos in citations, minor change

    On the Monadic Second-Order Transduction Hierarchy

    Full text link
    We compare classes of finite relational structures via monadic second-order transductions. More precisely, we study the preorder where we set C \subseteq K if, and only if, there exists a transduction {\tau} such that C\subseteq{\tau}(K). If we only consider classes of incidence structures we can completely describe the resulting hierarchy. It is linear of order type {\omega}+3. Each level can be characterised in terms of a suitable variant of tree-width. Canonical representatives of the various levels are: the class of all trees of height n, for each n \in N, of all paths, of all trees, and of all grids
    • …
    corecore