242 research outputs found
Mistaken Identity and Mirror Images: Albert and Carl Einstein, Leiden and Berlin, Relativity and Revolution
Albert Einstein accepted a 'special' visiting professorship at the University
of Leiden in the Netherlands in February 1920. Although his appointment should
have been a mere formality, it took until October of that year before Einstein
could occupy his special chair. Why the delay? The explanation involves a case
of mistaken identity with Carl Einstein, Dadaist art, and a particular Dutch
fear of revolutions. But what revolution was one afraid of? The story of
Einstein's Leiden chair throws new light on the reception of relativity and its
creator in the Netherlands and in Germany
Reactionaries and Einstein's Fame: "German Scientists for the Preservation of Pure Science," Relativity, and the Bad Nauheim Meeting
Two important and unpleasant events occurred in Albert Einstein's life in
1920: That August an antirelativity rally was held in the large auditorium of
the Berlin Philharmonic, and a few weeks later Einstein was drawn into a tense
and highly publicized debate with Philipp Lenard on the merits of relativity at
a meeting in Bad Nauheim, Germany. I review these events and discuss how they
affected Einstein in light of new documentary evidence that has become
available through the publication of Volume 10 of the Collected Papers of
Albert Einstein.Comment: 18 page
The reception of relativity in the Netherlands
This article reviews the early academic and public reception of Albert
Einstein's theory of relativity in the Netherlands, particularly after Arthur
Eddington's eclipse experiments of 1919. Initially, not much attention was
given to relativity, as it did not seem an improvement over Hendrik A. Lorentz'
work. This changed after the arrival in Leiden of Paul Ehrenfest. Soon
relativity was much studied and lead to controversy among a number of
conservative intellectuals, as elsewhere in Europe. The tone of Dutch critics
was much more mild, however. This can be understood when one considers Dutch
neutrality during World War I. Einstein's political positions were generally
positively perceived in Holland, which Dutch academics put to use in their
efforts at international reconciliation abroad, and the presentation of
theoretical physics at home
The Epistemic Virtues of the Virtuous Theorist: On Albert Einstein and His Autobiography
Albert Einstein’s practice in physics and his philosophical positions gradually reoriented themselves from more empiricist towards rationalist viewpoints. This change accompanied his turn towards unified field theory and different presentations of himself, eventually leading to his highly programmatic Autobiographical Notes in 1949. Einstein enlisted his own history and professional stature to mold an ideal of a theoretical physicist who represented particular epistemic virtues and moral qualities. These in turn reflected the theoretical ideas of his strongly mathematical unification program and professed Spinozist beliefs
Emil Rupp, Albert Einstein and the canal ray experiments on wave-particle duality: Scientific fraud and theoretical bias
In 1926 Emil Rupp published a number of papers on the interference properties
of light emitted by canal ray sources. These articles, particularly one paper
that came into being in collaboration with Albert Einstein, drew quite some
attention as they probed the wave versus particle nature of light. They also
significantly propelled Rupp's career, even though that from the outset they
were highly controversial. This article will review this episode, and in
particular Rupp's collaboration with Einstein. Evidence that Rupp forged his
results is presented and their critical reception in the socially and
politically divided German physics community is discussed. These divisions fail
to explain the full dynamic; the latter is attempted by turning to the role
that theoretical bias on occasion has in assessing experiment. Einstein's
responses in particular are analyzed in this context
Communicating the Heisenberg uncertainty relations: Niels Bohr, Complementarity and the Einstein-Rupp experiments
The Einstein-Rupp experiments have been unduly neglected in the history of
quantum mechanics. While this is to be explained by the fact that Emil Rupp was
later exposed as a fraud and had fabricated the results, it is not justified,
due to the importance attached to the experiments at the time. This paper
discusses Rupp's fraud, the relation between Albert Einstein and Rupp, and the
Einstein-Rupp experiments, and argues that these experiments were an influence
on Niels Bohr's development of complementarity and Werner Heisenberg's
formulation of the uncertainty relations.Comment: One Hundred Years of the Bohr Atom, 1913-2013. Conference at the
Royal Danish Academy of Sciences and Letters, Copenhagen, 11-14 June 2013.
Published as Scientia Danica. Series M, Mathematica et physica, 1: One
Hundred Years of the Bohr Atom, Proceedings, 2015, pp. 310-34
The interpretation of the Einstein-Rupp experiments and their influence on the history of quantum mechanics
The Einstein-Rupp experiments were proposed in 1926 by Albert Einstein to
study the wave versus particle nature of light. Einstein presented a
theoretical analysis of these experiments to the Berlin Academy together with
results of Emil Rupp, who claimed to have successfully carried them out.
However, as the preceding paper has claimed (HSPS 37 Suppl. (2007), 73-121),
Rupp's success was the result of scientific fraud. This paper will argue, after
exploring their interpretation, that the experiments were a relevant part of
the background to such celebrated contributions to quantum mechanics as Born's
statistical interpretation of the wave function and Heisenberg's uncertainty
principle. Yet, the Einstein-Rupp experiments have hardly received attention in
the history of quantum mechanics literature. In part, this is a consequence of
self-censorship in the physics community, enforced in the wake of the Rupp
affair. Self-censorship among historians of physics may however also have
played a role
In Europe
As the History of Science Society, which is based in America, holds its
annual meeting in Utrecht, one of the key academic centers on the European
continent, one may surmise that the field has returned home. Yet, this hardly
reflects how today's world of scholarship is constituted: in the historiography
of science, 'provincializing Europe' has become an important theme, while the
field itself, as is the case across the world of academia, is centered around a
predominantly American literature. At the same time, ever since historians of
science have emancipated themselves from the sciences a long time ago, they
often have appeared, in the public eye, to question rather than to seek to
bolster the authority of the sciences. How has this situation come about, and
what does it tell us about the world we live in today? What insight is sought
and what public benefit is gained by the historical study of science? As we try
to answer these questions, we will follow a number of key mid-twentieth century
historians--Eduard Dijksterhuis, Thomas Kuhn and Martin Klein--in their
Atlantic crossings. Their answers to debates on the constitution of the early
modern scientific revolution or the novelty of the work of Max Planck will
illustrate how notions of 'center' and 'periphery' have shifted--and what that
may tell us about being 'in Europe' today.Comment: Elizabeth Paris Lecture, History of Science Society meeting, Utrecht,
23-27 July 201
String theory, Einstein, and the identity of physics: Theory assessment in absence of the empirical
String theorists are certain that they are practicing physicists. Yet, some
of their recent critics deny this. This paper argues that this conflict is
really about who holds authority in making rational judgment in theoretical
physics. At bottom, the conflict centers on the question: who is a proper
physicist? To illustrate and understand the differing opinions about proper
practice and identity, we discuss different appreciations of epistemic virtues
and explanation among string theorists and their critics, and how these have
been sourced in accounts of Einstein's biography. Just as Einstein is claimed
by both sides, historiography offers examples of both successful and
unsuccessful non-empirical science. History of science also teaches that times
of conflict are often times of innovation, in which novel scholarly identities
may come into being. At the same time, since the contributions of Thomas Kuhn
historians have developed a critical attitude towards formal attempts and
methodological recipes for epistemic demarcation and justification of
scientific practice. These are now, however, being considered in the debate on
non-empirical physics.Comment: To appear in Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, special
issue on "Non-Empirical Physics from a Historical Perspective
- …