125 research outputs found
Philosophy of Experimental Biology
Philosophers have committed sins while studying science, it is said â philosophy of science focused on physics to the detriment of biology, reconstructed idealizations of scientific episodes rather than attending to historical details, and focused on theories and concepts to the detriment of experiments. Recent generations of philosophers of science have tried to atone for these sins, and by the 1980s the exculpation was in full swing. Marcel Weberâs Philosophy of Experimental Biology is a zenith mea culpa for philosophy of science: it carefully describes several historical examples from twentieth century biology to address both âoldâ philosophical topics, like reductionism, inference, and realism, and ânewâ topics, like discovery, models, and norms. Biology, experiments, history â at last, philosophy of science, free of sin
New Directions in Philosophy of Medicine
The purpose of this chapter is to describe what we see as several important new directions for philosophy of medicine. This recent work (i) takes existing discussions in important and promising new directions, (ii) identifies areas that have not received sufficient and deserved attention to date, and/or (iii) brings together philosophy of medicine with other areas of philosophy (including bioethics, philosophy of psychiatry, and social epistemology). To this end, the next part focuses on what we call the âepistemological turnâ in recent work in the philosophy of medicine; the third part addresses new developments in medical research that raise interesting questions for philosophy of medicine; the fourth part is a discussion of philosophical issues within the practice of diagnosis; the fifth part focuses on the recent developments in psychiatric classification and scientific and ethical issues therein, and the final part focuses on the objectivity of medical research
The Chemical Characterization of the Gene: Vicissitudes of Evidential Assessment
The chemical characterization of the substance responsible for the
phenomenon of âtransformationâ of pneumococci was presented in the now famous 1944
paper by Avery, MacLeod, and McCarty. Reception of this work was mixed. Although
interpreting their results as evidence that deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA) is the molecule
responsible for genetic changes was, at the time, controversial, this paper has been
retrospectively celebrated as providing such evidence. The mixed and changing assessment
of the evidence presented in the paper was due to the workâs interpretive flexibility â
the evidence was interpreted in various ways, and such interpretations were justified
given the neophytic state of molecular biology and methodological limitations of Averyâs
transformation studies. I argue that the changing context in which the evidence presented
by Averyâs group was interpreted partly explains the vicissitudes of the assessments of the
evidence. Two less compelling explanations of the reception are a myth-making account and
an appeal to the wartime historical context of its publication
Measuring effectiveness.
Measuring the effectiveness of medical interventions faces three epistemological challenges: the choice of good measuring instruments, the use of appropriate analytic measures, and the use of a reliable method of extrapolating measures from an experimental context to a more general context. In practice each of these challenges contributes to overestimating the effectiveness of medical interventions. These challenges suggest the need for corrective normative principles. The instruments employed in clinical research should measure patient-relevant and disease-specific parameters, and should not be sensitive to parameters that are only indirectly relevant. Effectiveness always should be measured and reported in absolute terms (using measures such as 'absolute risk reduction'), and only sometimes should effectiveness also be measured and reported in relative terms (using measures such as 'relative risk reduction')-employment of relative measures promotes an informal fallacy akin to the base-rate fallacy, which can be exploited to exaggerate claims of effectiveness. Finally, extrapolating from research settings to clinical settings should more rigorously take into account possible ways in which the intervention in question can fail to be effective in a target population
Evidence in biology and the conditions of success
Abstract I describe two traditions of philosophical accounts of evidence: one characterizes the notion in terms of signs of success, the other characterizes the notion in terms of conditions of success. The best examples of the former rely on the probability calculus, and have the virtues of generality and theoretical simplicity. The best examples of the latter describe the features of evidence which scientists appeal to in practice, which include general features of methods, such as quality and relevance, and general features of evidence, such as patterns in data, concordance with other evidence, and believability of the evidence. Two infamous episodes from biomedical research help to illustrate these features. Philosophical characterization of these latter featuresâconditions of successâhas the virtue of potential relevance to, and descriptive accuracy of, practices of experimental scientists
- âŠ