2,011 research outputs found
On the works of Euler and his followers on spherical geometry
We review and comment on some works of Euler and his followers on spherical
geometry. We start by presenting some memoirs of Euler on spherical
trigonometry. We comment on Euler's use of the methods of the calculus of
variations in spherical trigonometry. We then survey a series of geometrical
resuls, where the stress is on the analogy between the results in spherical
geometry and the corresponding results in Euclidean geometry. We elaborate on
two such results. The first one, known as Lexell's Theorem (Lexell was a
student of Euler), concerns the locus of the vertices of a spherical triangle
with a fixed area and a given base. This is the spherical counterpart of a
result in Euclid's Elements, but it is much more difficult to prove than its
Euclidean analogue. The second result, due to Euler, is the spherical analogue
of a generalization of a theorem of Pappus (Proposition 117 of Book VII of the
Collection) on the construction of a triangle inscribed in a circle whose sides
are contained in three lines that pass through three given points. Both results
have many ramifications, involving several mathematicians, and we mention some
of these developments. We also comment on three papers of Euler on projections
of the sphere on the Euclidean plane that are related with the art of drawing
geographical maps.Comment: To appear in Ganita Bharati (Indian Mathematics), the Bulletin of the
Indian Society for History of Mathematic
Vector constants of the motion and orbits in the Coulomb/Kepler problem
The equation for the conic sections describing the possible orbits in a
potential is obtained by means of a vector constant of the
motion differing from the traditional Laplace-Runge-Lenz vector.Comment: 5 pages, no figure
Maty's Biography of Abraham De Moivre, Translated, Annotated and Augmented
November 27, 2004, marked the 250th anniversary of the death of Abraham De
Moivre, best known in statistical circles for his famous large-sample
approximation to the binomial distribution, whose generalization is now
referred to as the Central Limit Theorem. De Moivre was one of the great
pioneers of classical probability theory. He also made seminal contributions in
analytic geometry, complex analysis and the theory of annuities. The first
biography of De Moivre, on which almost all subsequent ones have since relied,
was written in French by Matthew Maty. It was published in 1755 in the Journal
britannique. The authors provide here, for the first time, a complete
translation into English of Maty's biography of De Moivre. New material, much
of it taken from modern sources, is given in footnotes, along with numerous
annotations designed to provide additional clarity to Maty's biography for
contemporary readers.Comment: Published at http://dx.doi.org/10.1214/088342306000000268 in the
Statistical Science (http://www.imstat.org/sts/) by the Institute of
Mathematical Statistics (http://www.imstat.org
From Logical Calculus to Logical FormalityâWhat Kant Did with Eulerâs Circles
John Venn has the âuneasy suspicionâ that the stagnation in mathematical logic between J. H. Lambert and George Boole was due to Kantâs âdisastrous effect on logical method,â namely the âstrictest preservation [of logic] from mathematical encroachment.â Kantâs actual position is more nuanced, however. In this chapter, I tease out the nuances by examining his use of Leonhard Eulerâs circles and comparing it with Eulerâs own use. I do so in light of the developments in logical calculus from G. W. Leibniz to Lambert and Gottfried Ploucquet. While Kant is evidently open to using mathematical tools in logic, his main concern is to clarify what mathematical tools can be used to achieve. For without such clarification, all efforts at introducing mathematical tools into logic would be blind if not complete waste of time. In the end, Kant would stress, the means provided by formal logic at best help us to express and order what we already know in some sense. No matter how much mathematical notations may enhance the precision of this function of formal logic, it does not change the fact that no truths can, strictly speaking, be revealed or established by means of those notations
Leonhard Eulers Wege zur Zahlentheorie
Eine chronologische und kontextualisierende Uebersicht der zahlentheoretischen Arbeiten Leonhard Euler
A Tricentenary history of the Law of Large Numbers
The Weak Law of Large Numbers is traced chronologically from its inception as
Jacob Bernoulli's Theorem in 1713, through De Moivre's Theorem, to ultimate
forms due to Uspensky and Khinchin in the 1930s, and beyond. Both aspects of
Jacob Bernoulli's Theorem: 1. As limit theorem (sample size ), and:
2. Determining sufficiently large sample size for specified precision, for
known and also unknown p (the inversion problem), are studied, in frequentist
and Bayesian settings. The Bienaym\'{e}-Chebyshev Inequality is shown to be a
meeting point of the French and Russian directions in the history. Particular
emphasis is given to less well-known aspects especially of the Russian
direction, with the work of Chebyshev, Markov (the organizer of Bicentennial
celebrations), and S.N. Bernstein as focal points.Comment: Published in at http://dx.doi.org/10.3150/12-BEJSP12 the Bernoulli
(http://isi.cbs.nl/bernoulli/) by the International Statistical
Institute/Bernoulli Society (http://isi.cbs.nl/BS/bshome.htm
- âŠ